04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Balancing and the limitation of rights in the South African Constitution 259<br />

distinction between rules and principles is a basic pillar in the edifice of<br />

constitutional rights theory’. 42 His next step is the characterisation of principles<br />

as ‘optimisation requirements’, ‘norms which require that something be realised<br />

to the greatest extent possible given the legal and factual possibilities’. Unlike<br />

rules, which are definitive commands, norms ‘which are always either fulfilled<br />

or not’, principles can be ‘satisfied to varying degrees’ depending on what is<br />

factually and legally possible in a particular case. 43 A constitutional rule is<br />

therefore something like section 49(1) of the Constitution – ‘The National<br />

Assembly is elected for a term of five years’ – or section 79(5) – ‘If the<br />

Constitutional Court decides that the Bill is constitutional, the President must<br />

assent to it and sign it’ – or section 5 – ‘The national flag of the Republic is<br />

black, gold, green, white, red and blue ...’ The application of rules like these<br />

entails subsumption. If a rule is valid and applicable, it is required to do exactly<br />

what it demands be done. If <strong>this</strong> is done, the rule is complied with; if <strong>this</strong> is not<br />

done, the rule is not complied with. 44 A constitutional principle, on the other<br />

hand, is relatively easily identified since the Constitution self-consciously<br />

characterises some of its provisions as such: for example, the ‘Principles of Cooperative<br />

Governance’ listed in section 41, or the ‘Basic Values and Principles<br />

Governing Public Administration’ in section 195. It is also exemplified by any<br />

of the rights in the Bill of Rights, since each right is notionally subject to the<br />

possibility of limitation in terms of the general limitation section. 45 ‘Everyone<br />

has the right to privacy’ seems on the face of it to state a rule, but in fact it does<br />

not since we know that it does not state a categorical prohibition on restrictions<br />

of privacy; privacy can in fact be restricted in the service of countervailing,<br />

constitutionally-recognised considerations such as public safety or the detection<br />

and prosecution of crime or to give effect to competing rights such as freedom<br />

of expression. Constitutional rights therefore have the structure of principles<br />

since they state what ought to be realised to the greatest extent relative to what<br />

is legally and factually possible. The legal possibilities are determined largely<br />

by competing principles, the factual by the facts of the case to be decided.<br />

Conflict between rules can arise and is resolved in one of two ways:<br />

Either an exception is read into one of the rules, or one of the rules is<br />

declared invalid. 46<br />

Competing principles are not resolved <strong>this</strong> way but instead by<br />

operation of a characteristic of principles that, as Dworkin noticed, is not<br />

possessed by rules – the dimension of weight:<br />

42<br />

R Alexy Theory of constitutional rights (n 35 above) 44. There are no other norms,<br />

according to Alexy, ‘Every norm is either a rule or a principle’ 48.<br />

43 Alexy Theory of constitutional rights (n 35 above) 48 - 49.<br />

44<br />

Subsumption involves the comparison of abstract norms with the concrete facts in a<br />

given case to determine the applicability of the norms. R Alexy ‘On balancing and<br />

subsumption: A structural comparison’ (2003) 16 Ratio Juris 433.<br />

45<br />

‘Notionally’ because the general limitation section is not quite as general as it seems.<br />

See Woolman & Botha (n 24 above) 34.4 on the problem of internal modifiers in the<br />

formulation of some of the rights. There are also, here and there, rules in the Bill of<br />

Rights, eg sec 25(9) ‘Parliament must enact the legislation referred to in subsection (6)’.<br />

46 Alexy Theory of constitutional rights (n 35 above) 49.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!