04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

270 Chapter 12<br />

Schauer similarly conceives of rights as ‘shields’. 14 All these conceptions<br />

of rights seek to highlight the normative weight of fundamental rights in<br />

relation to other competing normative considerations and which explain<br />

their special place within the constitutional order.<br />

Alexy puts forward a structural account of rights as ‘optimisation<br />

principles’. The problem posed by a number of theorists is whether his<br />

theory is capable of capturing the special normative weight of<br />

constitutional rights in relation to other competing considerations. 15 It is<br />

necessary to outline briefly Alexy’s account of rights in order to engage<br />

with <strong>this</strong> criticism. 16<br />

Rights, according to Alexy, are principles rather than rules. Rules are<br />

norms that are always either fulfilled or not; whereas principles are ‘norms<br />

which require that something be realised to the greatest extent possible<br />

given the legal and factual possibilities’. 17 This characterisation of<br />

principles has implications for how to deal with conflicts between them: It<br />

means that where they conflict, one principle has to be weighed against the<br />

other. In <strong>this</strong> process, one of the principles may be outweighed by the<br />

other. 18 Alexy contends that <strong>this</strong> process is governed by the principle of<br />

proportionality: Indeed, ‘the nature of principles implies the principle of<br />

proportionality’. 19 As Currie points out, Alexy attempts to provide a<br />

rational justification for the way in which proportionality assessments are<br />

conducted in constitutional law as well an analytical structure that renders<br />

the process less subjective.<br />

Proportionality, Alexy claims, has a number of sub-principles: Two of<br />

these relate to more empirical matters. First, a particular measure that<br />

purports to restrict the realisation of a right must be closely connected to<br />

the realisation of another normative principle. This is the requirement of<br />

suitability: The South African Constitution incorporates <strong>this</strong> idea in section<br />

36(1) by requiring that there be a close connection between the limitation of<br />

a right and the purpose it seeks to achieve. Secondly, flowing from the idea<br />

of rights as optimisation principles is also the requirement of necessity: This<br />

entails that if there are a number of measures that would equally give effect<br />

to a particular principle then the measure that would be least intrusive of<br />

competing normative principles must be chosen. 20<br />

The other key element of proportionality in Alexy’s account relates to<br />

what he terms the realm of legal possibility: This involves the idea of<br />

14<br />

F Schauer ‘A comment on the structure of rights’ (1993) Georgia LR 429.<br />

15 See Meyerson (n 11 above) 814 and M Kumm ‘Political liberalism and the structure of<br />

rights’ in G Pavlakos (ed) Law, rights and discourse (2007) 142.<br />

16<br />

Currie has elaborated upon <strong>this</strong> in more depth in his paper and so I simply present a<br />

summary of the key points relevant to the argument here.<br />

17 Alexy (n 6 above) 47.<br />

18<br />

Alexy (n 6 above) 50.<br />

19 Alexy (n 6 above) 66.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!