04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

54 Chapter 2<br />

to facilitate public involvement in the legislative process; 72 to decide<br />

whether an official in the public administration has complied with the right<br />

to just administrative action and PAJA; 73 and so forth.<br />

But why does the rationality principle apply as a general baseline while<br />

the standard of reasonableness applies in a more restricted fashion?<br />

Here is an answer. On the one hand, the principle of comity obliges<br />

courts to respect the decisions of the political branches of the state in all<br />

circumstances. Usually, only the relatively deferential standard of rationality<br />

is compatible with <strong>this</strong> ever present duty. 74 On the other hand, certain laws<br />

and state conduct trigger vital individual and collective interests in a way that<br />

calls for special attention. The most obvious examples are those acts and laws<br />

that threaten or limit fundamental rights. The higher reasonableness standard<br />

is appropriate in these circumstances because the engaged interests are of such<br />

normative importance that they partially offset the courts’ countervailing duty<br />

to respect the political autonomy of the executive and legislature. This duty<br />

is never totally outweighed, though, as is reflected in the distinction the law<br />

draws between judging acts as reasonable and judging acts as justified or<br />

correct. 75<br />

The second form of variability of judicial scrutiny of law and conduct is<br />

within the standards of review. This is obvious in the case of reasonableness, as<br />

different factors of variable weight must be assessed in different contexts. The<br />

greater the potential or actual adverse effects of the law or conduct in question,<br />

the stronger the required countervailing reasons militating in its favour. This<br />

variability was expressly recognised by O’Regan J in Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v<br />

Minister of Environmental Affairs. 76<br />

Less well recognised, however, and more subtle is variability within<br />

rationality review. To recall, that principle requires that the law or conduct<br />

in question, once appropriately specified, first have an appropriate purpose<br />

(the purpose requirement) and, secondly, serve that purpose sufficiently well<br />

in order to be ‘rationally connected’ to it (the effect requirement). The wide<br />

variety of circumstances to which <strong>this</strong> test applies, the discretion its application<br />

involves, and the courts’ duty to apply it in a manner that respects the<br />

autonomy of the political branches of the state inevitably, and rightly, call<br />

for a degree of variability.<br />

72<br />

Doctors for Life International v Speaker of the National Assembly 2006 6 SA 416 (CC) paras 118 -<br />

129, 204; Matatiele Municipality v President of South Africa 2007 6 SA 477 (CC) paras 36 - 40,<br />

45.<br />

73<br />

Bato Star Fishing (n 34 above) para 44.<br />

74 This is exactly the point that Bishop (n 5 above) questions in general. I have already<br />

explained why the claim that rationality review is compatible with the principle of<br />

comity is intelligible. I argue that that claim is justified below, from 58.<br />

75 Note that sec 36 empowers courts to determine whether limitations to rights are<br />

‘reasonable and justifiable’ (my emphasis), not justified. The distinction, albeit a fine<br />

one, is important.<br />

76 Bato Star (n 34 above) para 45.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!