04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Does balancing adequately capture the nature of rights? 283<br />

means’ component is an ‘important part of the limitation analysis’ but that it<br />

is ‘only one consideration relevant to that analysis’. 60 This factor requires ‘a<br />

careful analysis of the purpose of the provision’ that is being impugned. 61 The<br />

judgment then goes on to quote Blackmun J in the US who famously wrote that<br />

‘[a] judge would be unimaginative indeed if he could not come up with<br />

something a little less “drastic” or a little less “restrictive” in almost any situation,<br />

and thereby enable himself to vote to strike the legislation down’. 62 This<br />

argument leads the judgment to recognise that the legislature adopts the<br />

particular measures it does in light of ‘concerns relating to cost, practical<br />

implementation, the prioritisation of certain social demands and needs and<br />

the need to reconcile conflicting interests’. 63 The legislature, the judges hold,<br />

is the appropriate institution to make difficult policy choices and the court<br />

should ‘take care to avoid a result that annihilates the range of choice<br />

available to the legislature. In particular, it should take care not to dictate to<br />

the legislature unless it is satisfied that the mechanism chosen by the<br />

legislature is incompatible with the Constitution’. 64<br />

The latter claim of course does not help solve the problem as the<br />

question is when a particular measure limiting a right is in fact<br />

incompatible with the Constitution, and the less restrictive means<br />

requirement is meant to assist in determining <strong>this</strong> issue. Woolman and<br />

Botha, however, capture the difficulty being gestured towards by the judges<br />

in <strong>this</strong> passage when they understand its concern to mean that ‘less restrictive<br />

means can often be envisaged, but such means may impose significant<br />

administrative burdens on the state, have other substantial cost implications,<br />

undermine the state’s symbolic objectives or reverse a hierarchy of needs<br />

worked out through the political process’. 65 The difficulty lies in determining<br />

when a court should strike down a measure where less restrictive means<br />

exist despite the fact that there would be costs to the political community in<br />

doing so. The way in which the Constitutional Court has sought to resolve<br />

<strong>this</strong> problem (although not in an entirely clear and satisfactory manner) can<br />

be gleaned through the following important dictum of Kriegler J:<br />

Where section 36(1)(e) speaks of less restrictive means it does not postulate an<br />

unattainable norm of perfection. The standard is reasonableness. And in any<br />

event, in theory less restrictive means can almost invariably be imagined<br />

without necessarily precluding a finding of justification under the section. It is<br />

but one of the enumerated considerations which have to be weighed in<br />

conjunction with one another, and with any others that may be relevant. 66<br />

60<br />

Manamela (n 57 above) para 94.<br />

61 Manamela (n 57 above) para 96.<br />

62 Manamela (n 57 above); Illinois State Board of Elections v Socialist Workers Party et al 440<br />

US 173 (1979) 188 - 189<br />

63 Manamela (n 57 above) para 95.<br />

64 As above.<br />

65<br />

Woolman & Botha (n 1 above) 34 - 89.<br />

66 S v Mamabolo 2001 3 SA 409 (CC) para 49.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!