04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

278 Chapter 12<br />

The latter claim could be broken down into the following elements: First,<br />

in the absence of a competing principle, the principle requires complete<br />

realisation. If we have a right to privacy implicated in a particular case and<br />

no competing principle, then that right must be realised in those particular<br />

circumstances. Secondly, where there are competing principles, the<br />

principle of proportionality will determine the outcome (with its subprinciples<br />

of necessity, suitability and balancing): Ultimately, though, the<br />

notion of principles as optimisation requirements means that the outcome<br />

must be adopted that allows for the greatest possible realisation of each<br />

principle so far as <strong>this</strong> is compatible (both factually and legally) with the<br />

greatest realisation of the others. 48<br />

It is important to recognise that Alexy’s language is metaphorical. The<br />

notion of ‘optimisation’ in a field such as economics, where clear<br />

quantification is possible, has a clear meaning: We clearly understand what<br />

it means, for instance, to optimise profit. However, the exact meaning of<br />

<strong>this</strong> term in the legal or moral context is less clear as the principles and<br />

values to be evaluated and balanced are not clearly quantifiable in the same<br />

manner. 49<br />

A crucial notion in understanding what optimisation means in the legal<br />

context is the idea of ‘possibility’. 50 When referring to what is legally<br />

possible, Alexy seems to be employing the idea of logical possibility. 51<br />

However, it remains unclear exactly what he means by the idea of factual<br />

possibility: Does <strong>this</strong> refer only to the outer limits of physical possibility (a<br />

measure cannot involve requiring humans to fly as they are not able to do<br />

so without being aided by an aircraft) or does <strong>this</strong> notion include constraints<br />

such as economic scarcity (a measure is unaffordable for a country given<br />

current lending policies, although it could be affordable if these policies<br />

changed) or political sensitivity (a measure cannot be passed as it will cause<br />

massive protests and civil disobedience if it is)? Determining what is included<br />

within the realm of factual possibility will be critical for determining the<br />

extent to which a principle can be realised or not and thus be a crucial factor<br />

in the application of the principle of proportionality. Without clarifying what<br />

is meant by possibility, the balancing process may not lead to determinate<br />

outcomes as it will not be clear what is meant by realising a principle to the<br />

‘greatest extent possible’. Moreover, if the account of possibility that Alexy<br />

gives is too strong (such as conceiving factual possibility as the outer limits of<br />

physical possibility), then it would render it extremely difficult to justify the<br />

limitation of fundamental rights even in cases where <strong>this</strong> seems intuitively to<br />

be reasonable.<br />

48<br />

K Moller ‘Balancing and the structure of constitutional rights’ (2007) 6 Int J of Constitutional<br />

Law 453 459.<br />

49 Moller (n 48 above) 462.<br />

50<br />

Moller (n 48 above) 459.<br />

51 Alexy (n 6 above) 51 - 53.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!