04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

388 Chapter 16<br />

as to how empiricism and an experimental approach helps in the quest to<br />

explicate normative questions.<br />

Woolman also fails to recognise a clear tension between his approval<br />

of experimental constitutionalism and his critique of minimalism. Indeed, in<br />

laying out his version of experimental constitutionalism, he contends that<br />

‘the process of general norm-setting by the courts that initiates a process of<br />

rolling best practices by other parts of the state never gains sufficient traction<br />

when constitutional norms remain radically under-theorised’. 90 However,<br />

the problem is that the more detailed a court’s norm-setting prescriptions are,<br />

the less room is left for experimentation and finding out ‘what works best’. A<br />

defender of the minimalist approach to adjudication would argue that one of<br />

its chief virtues is precisely the use of narrow adjudicative techniques that<br />

leave open the possibility of change in the future. This incremental approach<br />

would allow one to test a particular norm in a narrow way and allow<br />

flexibility for modification in the future. The more detailed and<br />

comprehensive the norm setting of the courts the less flexibility there would<br />

be in future and the less room there would be for shared constitutional<br />

interpretation and participatory bubbles to make a difference. Experimental<br />

constitutionalism thus seems to support a minimalist approach to<br />

adjudication rather than providing an alternative to it.<br />

Our argument is not that experimental constitutionalism as articulated<br />

by Woolman does not have a number of virtues nor that it can never provide<br />

a useful methodology in constitutional matters. However, we contend that it is<br />

an incomplete method in the realm of law and fails to provide us with a<br />

deeper understanding of the relationship between theory and practice in <strong>this</strong><br />

domain. Recognition of the distinctive features of legal adjudicative<br />

practices is what is needed. We have argued that judges are inevitably<br />

required to engage in the realm of normative reasoning and that,<br />

consequently, the method that is required is one akin to that adopted in the<br />

realm of political philosophy where a reflective equilibrium is sought between<br />

considered convictions and theoretical understandings. New circumstances<br />

will of course disrupt an easy equilibrium and require the revision of<br />

settled doctrine. Adjudicative practices are also essentially interpretive<br />

which requires a greater degree of abstract reasoning than more applied<br />

practices. An experimental approach to institutional structures and possibly<br />

even rules may be consistent with <strong>this</strong> method. However, any account of<br />

adjudicative practice cannot be ‘experimentalist’, ‘pragmatist’, or ‘empiricist’<br />

alone and must include an understanding of the role that normative<br />

reasoning plays in the development of law and its distinctive<br />

methodologies.<br />

90 Dworkin (n 1 above) 25.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!