04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Kibitzing with Frank Michelman on how to best read the Constitutional Court 401<br />

4 How best to understand the case for clarity<br />

One can describe the problem of thinness in South African constitutional<br />

law in a number of different ways. Here is how I would state the problem:<br />

Thinly reasoned judgments presuppose that the current information deficit in<br />

deciding a matter – and the concomitant limits placed upon doctrinal<br />

development – will at least partially be ameliorated as time and experience<br />

throw up new opportunities to expand our understanding of how specific<br />

substantive rights ought to function in given environments. The<br />

Constitutional Court’s ongoing failure to develop coherent doctrines in a<br />

significant number of areas of fundamental rights jurisprudence places the<br />

Court’s very authority at risk. Moreover, the absence of clearly articulated<br />

rules undermines rational political discourse. Reasoned disagreement can only<br />

take place when parties agree on the general terms of the debate. The<br />

Constitutional Court must, in terms of its institutional role, establish the<br />

meaning of constitutional norms and thus the general framework for political<br />

contestation. The Constitutional Court abdicates <strong>this</strong> institutional<br />

responsibility to model rational political discourse by refusing to state, in a<br />

comprehensive manner, the reasons that ground its conclusions.<br />

Professor Michelman is unlikely to concur with <strong>this</strong> assessment of the<br />

Court’s work. In any event, neither of us has claimed nor felt it necessary to<br />

defend the Court against the claim that it has systematically failed to offer<br />

reasoned accounts for its decisions. The former position would be ludicrous;<br />

the latter position unnecessary. Instead, in the pages that follow, I want to<br />

allow other voices to break in to <strong>this</strong> conversation – from the bench, from the<br />

podium, from the academy – to offer their assessment on the thinness and the<br />

clarity of the Court’s judgments.<br />

4.1 Voices from the bench<br />

Constitutional Court Justice Edwin Cameron has agreed, at least in part,<br />

with my rather abstract characterisation of some of the Constitutional<br />

Court’s judgments as thin, and lacking in clarity. 25 Cameron J (then of the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal in 2009) writes:<br />

At <strong>this</strong> tender stage of our legal development, the doctrine of precedent has special<br />

importance. The CC has been accused of disregarding its own decisions without<br />

convincing reason (without, indeed, acknowledging that it has done so). That is<br />

a grave charge … [And] <strong>this</strong> means that other courts, including the SCA, must follow<br />

25<br />

True Motives v Mahdi (543/07) [2009] ZASCA 4 para 102, n 53 citing Woolman<br />

‘Amazing’ (n 1 above).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!