04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Theory, practice and the legal enterprise 375<br />

layers of theory that are nascent within the law. 26 Dworkin attempts to<br />

capture <strong>this</strong> idea through the notion of ‘justificatory ascent’. To understand<br />

<strong>this</strong> idea, one can usefully begin by considering adjudication by his fictional<br />

superhero judge Hercules. Hercules would essentially have a grand theory of<br />

everything and could deduce the solution to each particular case from the most<br />

abstract of philosophical principles down to the finest detail. 27 As mere mortal<br />

lawyers with limited capacities, Dworkin recognises that the rest of us must<br />

usually approach legal decision making the other way round, moving from<br />

concrete cases towards more abstract principles in a process Dworkin terms<br />

‘justificatory ascent’. 28 Justificatory ascent involves the idea that the concrete<br />

principles in the area of law with which one is concerned may not answer<br />

the particular question before a judge. To provide an adequate response, the<br />

judge may need to engage other areas of law. In some cases, <strong>this</strong> will involve<br />

understanding and engaging with political philosophy concerning the most<br />

desirable approach to achieve justice in a particular case. From a particular<br />

concrete case, a judge may be pushed to higher levels of abstract theory in order<br />

to provide a compelling justification to decide the case in a particular way.<br />

Contrary to the claims of Posner, for instance, Dworkin argues that no one can<br />

determine in advance the degree of ascent that is necessary for any particular<br />

decision and <strong>this</strong> will be dependent upon the context and the particular case at<br />

hand. In summary, he argues that ‘legal reasoning presupposes a vast<br />

domain of justification including very abstract principles of political<br />

morality, that we tend to take that structure as much for granted as the<br />

engineer takes most of what he knows for granted, but that we might be<br />

forced to reexamine some part of that structure from time to time, though we<br />

can never be sure, in advance, when and how’. 29<br />

Justificatory ascent does appear to capture in part some of our intuitions<br />

as to how theory enters adjudication. Yet, we wish to highlight two particular<br />

problems with it. The first involves showing why the ascent to a Herculean level<br />

of abstraction is not necessary in every case. In other words, every legal case<br />

will involve some consideration of applicable legal provisions. This will<br />

involve at least some considerations of language as well as certain normative<br />

considerations of justice. As such, every case would arguably invoke at least<br />

potentially complex questions of language and justice. It is unclear the basis<br />

upon which Dworkin claims judges may justifiably ascend to higher levels of<br />

abstract theory only in some cases and not others. It may be, for instance,<br />

that a particular case is a simple application of a particular legal rule. Even<br />

26<br />

The literature on <strong>this</strong> topic is vast; see Dworkin (n 1 above) 36 - 48 for a discussion of<br />

some of <strong>this</strong> literature with regard to legal theory. Posner (n 13 above) 377 accuses<br />

Dworkin of failing adequately to explain what is meant by theory in law.<br />

27<br />

Dworkin (n 20 above) 358.<br />

28 Dworkin (n 20 above) 358 - 359. Woolman’s charge that Dworkin somehow seeks to<br />

discover a transcendent, higher reality is puzzling given that Dworkin expressly<br />

criticises such theories in the first chapter of Justice in robes. Similarly, Woolman’s claims<br />

about how Dworkin (and those who reify theory) engage with empirical evidence would<br />

seem to be contradicted by Dworkin’s statements about the inside-out method (see<br />

below).<br />

29 Dworkin (n 20 above) 56.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!