04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Balancing and the limitation of rights in the South African Constitution 253<br />

prosecuting and preventing crime’. 10 By contrast, the unanimous conclusion<br />

of the European Court was that the balance went the other way. It was<br />

found that ‘the blanket and indiscriminate nature of the powers of retention of<br />

the fingerprints, cellular samples and DNA profiles of persons suspected<br />

but not convicted of offences, as applied in the case of the present<br />

applicants, fails to strike a fair balance between the competing public and<br />

private interests’. 11<br />

Under the South African Constitution, it is certainly an arguable<br />

proposition that retention of DNA data and cellular samples in a forensic<br />

database is constitutionally permissible, despite its infringement of the<br />

right to privacy. The argument in a constitutional challenge is likely to<br />

proceed in much the same way as outlined above. What then does it mean<br />

to say, as section 14 of the Constitution does, that ‘everyone has the right<br />

to privacy’? What exactly is it that <strong>this</strong> declaration achieves if the right can<br />

simply be balanced against the interests of crime detection and prevention<br />

and, as the decisions of the UK courts illustrate, may be outweighed by these<br />

policy goals? If rights can be weighed against competing public interests<br />

justifying their restriction, and if they are sometimes outweighed by those<br />

interests, then it is not clear what is gained by having a right. This conception<br />

of rights is at odds with a conception of rights as having special strength and<br />

significance, with the idea that, if they are to be taken seriously, rights<br />

should not simply be traded against competing policy goals. 12<br />

2 The ubiquity of balancing<br />

The principle of proportionality which is the hallmark of the jurisprudence<br />

of the European Court of Human Rights and of the UK courts under the<br />

Human Rights Act is also the principle governing the practice of the South<br />

African courts under the 1996 Constitution. In the latter case, <strong>this</strong> is because<br />

of the presence of the limitation section in the South African Constitution,<br />

which provides that the rights in the Bill of Rights can be limited by law if<br />

there are good reasons for doing so. 13 The limitation section sets out criteria<br />

for determining what constitutes a good reason for limiting rights. These are<br />

the criteria in the part of the general formula beginning with the words ‘the<br />

limitation is reasonable and justifiable in an open and democratic society<br />

based on human dignity, equality and freedom’ and the first three limitation<br />

10<br />

R (Marper) v Chief Constable of the South Yorkshire Police [2002] EWCA Civ 1275, quoted by<br />

the ECtHR (n 6 above) 13.<br />

11 Marper (ECtHR) (n 6 above) 125.<br />

12<br />

M Kumm ‘Political liberalism and the structure of rights’ in G Pavlakos (ed) Law, rights<br />

and discourse: The legal philosophy of Robert Alexy (2007) 131. According to Kumm, the<br />

general conception of rights in the liberal tradition is that rights may not be overridden<br />

by ordinary considerations of policy. This formulation unites Dworkin’s conception of<br />

rights as ‘trumps’, Rawls’s notion of the priority of the right over the good and<br />

Habermas’s conception of rights as having a deontological character that withdraws<br />

them from participation in a cost-benefit analysis.<br />

13 Sec 36 of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!