04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

374 Chapter 16<br />

abstract theories in their judgments. Prominent critics of <strong>this</strong> view include<br />

Posner who is against the development of such overarching theories: law in<br />

his view is essentially a practical enterprise aimed at making the best decision<br />

in particular circumstances and requires rather an orientation towards<br />

ensuring the best consequences overall for a decision. 21 Here it is quite clear<br />

that Posner assumes a particular theory as to how judges should go about<br />

deciding cases (a point he admits). 22 The claim, however, by such critics is<br />

not that theory can be eliminated from law but rather that it should be<br />

minimised and kept at the ‘lowest’ level of abstraction. 23 The problem with<br />

<strong>this</strong> view is that it is difficult to see why theory should be confined to the<br />

‘lowest’ level of abstraction and what <strong>this</strong> prescription actually means.<br />

Indeed, failing to engage abstractly with theory may simply mean that judges<br />

are less aware of the shortcomings of any particular approach they adopt.<br />

Higher levels of abstract thinking may in fact improve the performance of<br />

judges in relation to concrete cases. It is thus unclear how one can defend a<br />

practice that generally seeks to avoid further abstract philosophical reflection,<br />

even where <strong>this</strong> may improve the the quality of decisions.<br />

This criticism requires us to recognise different types of theories that<br />

exist in relation to the law. 24 First, there are theories about the law, for<br />

example, theories about what the nature of law consists in, such as positivism,<br />

and natural law. These theories aim to explain the nature of law and may<br />

deepen a judge’s understanding of what she is doing. They are not though<br />

necessarily required for reaching a particular result in a concrete case.<br />

Secondly, there are a whole host of moral, political, social, metaphysical and<br />

epistemological theories that underlie and shape the law. These theories are<br />

‘embedded’ in the law 25 and they give the legal system its shape and content.<br />

This group contains both grand over-arching theories of, for example, the<br />

purpose and functioning of a state as well as more specific theories about<br />

more particular issues such as the justification for the existence of a particular<br />

right. Finally, theory also involves the notion of legal doctrine where<br />

academics or judges, for instance, draw out general principles from specific<br />

cases. Doctrine can involve specific theoretical underpinnings of principles<br />

and/or even a collection of those very principles that systematise a particular<br />

area of the law.<br />

The law itself thus is connected to theory in different ways and at different<br />

levels of abstraction. This idea may be captured by recognising different<br />

21<br />

Posner has advanced his judicial philosophy in a number of monographs, most<br />

recently and comprehensively in How judges think (2008).<br />

22 See Posner (n 13 above) 377.<br />

23<br />

A similar point is made in C Sunstein ‘From theory to practice’ (1997) Arizona State LJ 389<br />

24<br />

391 - 395.<br />

We do not deny there may be other forms of theory, yet, we attempt to categorise the<br />

25<br />

forms of theory most in evidence in the law.<br />

Dworkin (n 20 above) 355 - 357.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!