04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

298 Chapter 13<br />

Canadian courts would consequently be far less likely to defer easily to<br />

parliament or the executive in deciding issues of policy than their English<br />

counterparts.<br />

The South African Constitution explicitly includes socio-economic<br />

rights, and these rights have, from the outset, been accepted as justiciable. 33<br />

Courts have not, therefore accepted arguments that socio-economic rights are<br />

not justiciable on the basis of constitutional competence arguments, since<br />

courts are not democratically mandated to decide issues of socio-economic<br />

policy. Such arguments are, however, nonetheless relevant to the manner<br />

in which socio-economic rights matters are decided and the relief which is<br />

given.<br />

2.2 Institutional competence<br />

The second consideration underpinning a court’s approach to deference<br />

relates to perceived institutional limitations in the various branches of<br />

government, and is based on a ‘practical evaluation of the capacity of<br />

decision making bodies to make certain decisions’. 34 For Lord Steyn, the<br />

‘relative institutional capacity’ of the courts is the critical factor in deciding<br />

whether courts should defer to the other branches of government. 35 This<br />

consideration is given further weight in the modern bureaucratic state<br />

with its reliance on specialist expertise in almost all areas of the<br />

government machine. As a result, some have argued that it is<br />

inappropriate for courts to engage in review of complex government<br />

policy, or ‘polycentric decision making’, as judges lack the experience,<br />

knowledge or resources to make these types of decisions, in particular, to<br />

assess what the consequences of their decisions may be and to respond<br />

flexibly to unanticipated results of those decisions. For the same reasons, as<br />

a general rule, courts will be far more willing to defer to other agencies where<br />

the matter is one of fact or policy rather than of law or constitutional<br />

interpretation.<br />

It is important to note from the outset that, as with the other<br />

factors underpinning constitutional deference, the question of institutional<br />

capacity is based on the perceived appropriateness of the courts to make<br />

certain types of decisions, rather than an inherent inability to make these<br />

decisions. In principle, there are very few, if any, decisions which a court<br />

cannot make, if given enough time and information. In commenting on a<br />

33<br />

Ex Parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly: In re Certification of the Constitution of the<br />

Republic of South Africa, 1996 1996 4 SA 744 (CC) para 77.<br />

34 Jowell (n 2 above) 330.<br />

35<br />

Lord Steyn ‘Deference: A tangled story’ (2005) Public Law 346 352. See also J Jowell<br />

‘Judicial deference and human rights: A question of competence’ in P Craig &<br />

R Rawlings (eds) Law and administration in Europe: Essays in honour of Carol Harlow<br />

(2003) 67 80; J Jowell ‘Judicial deference: Servility, civility or institutional capacity?’<br />

(2003) Public Law 592 598.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!