04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

62 Chapter 2<br />

Do these costs outweigh rationality review’s benefits, thereby<br />

rendering it unjustified in principle? I think not, for there are at least three<br />

reasons why we should not exaggerate the costs. First, because the<br />

rationality principle applies across such a broad range of contexts, it has to<br />

be structured in an open-ended way that calls for case-specific judgments.<br />

It would be impossible for courts to guard against arbitrariness in<br />

legislation and the exercise of public power by applying a more rigid rule.<br />

For <strong>this</strong> reason, the flexible, discretionary character of rationality review is<br />

part of its value. This suggests that it is mistaken to claim that ‘[t]he traditional<br />

underpinnings of rational basis review … demand a test that forces<br />

predictable outcomes and removes personal discretion’. 104 Secondly, we<br />

should also not over-exaggerate the uncertainty of rationality review. The<br />

law instructs all political decision makers to act and legislate in a manner<br />

that serves a legitimate purpose. That, in itself, is significant guidance. In<br />

addition, although it is possible that different judges may exercise discretion<br />

under rationality review inconsistently, the risk of contradictory decisions<br />

remaining in the law reports is reduced by the fact that only the<br />

Constitutional Court can finally invalidate law or the conduct of the<br />

President. 105 Furthermore, the respect the Court owes the political<br />

branches under the principle of comity suggests that laws and conduct<br />

should be declared invalid only rarely. 106 Finally, as my account of the duty<br />

not to ‘second-guess’ the decisions of the executive and legislature makes<br />

clear, 107 courts are not permitted to evaluate and approve or disapprove<br />

of political decision-making in an entirely open-ended way; instead, they<br />

must sometimes exercise a constrained discretion to guard against an<br />

egregious, and therefore hopefully rare, evil – state arbitrariness or<br />

irrationality.<br />

For all these reasons, it is far from obvious that rationality review is<br />

unjustified in principle. The promotion of public reason could hardly be<br />

more valuable, and empowering courts to guard against irrational laws<br />

and acts contributes to <strong>this</strong> end. Introducing a degree of legal uncertainty<br />

and empowering judges to evaluate political choices in order to draw the<br />

outer boundaries of legitimate state decision making is arguably a fair price<br />

to pay. Imperfect legal guidance and a limited invasion of the state’s<br />

political autonomy are not obviously disproportionate to the moral gains on<br />

offer, in the form of promoting adherence to public reason.<br />

4.3 The rule of law as a justification<br />

The final matter to be addressed in <strong>this</strong> part is the courts’ frequent claim<br />

104 Bishop (n 5 above) 9.<br />

105 Sec 167(5) of the Constitution.<br />

106<br />

See the discussion in part 5 below.<br />

107 Sec 3.2.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!