04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Rationaliy is dead! Long live rationality! Saving rational basis review 11<br />

be brought to a screeching halt. However, the effect of requiring <strong>this</strong><br />

balance is that the test is necessarily influenced by judicial discretion and<br />

ceases to be a formal, logical exercise.<br />

To repeat, the test is: The differentiation is rationally connected to a<br />

legitimate government purpose. The four parts of the test are:<br />

(a) What is the differentiation or law at issue?<br />

(b) What is the purpose it serves?<br />

(c) Is that purpose legitimate?<br />

(d) If so, is the differentiation connected to the purpose?<br />

For reasons that I trust will become clear, I will consider these steps in more<br />

or less reverse order.<br />

4.1 Legitimacy 52<br />

The first element of the test is to determine which purposes are ‘legitimate’.<br />

In the traditional model of rational basis review <strong>this</strong> element operates as the<br />

door to the formal rationality check made up by the remaining three parts.<br />

However, as I explained earlier, that relationship can also be switched so<br />

that the rationality check becomes a mechanism to determine which<br />

purposes should be measured against the bar of legitimacy. Whether it<br />

functions as a threshold or a final arbiter, extreme approaches to the<br />

question of legitimacy pose perhaps the most blatant dangers to the validity<br />

of rational basis review.<br />

The first extreme occurs when a court accepts virtually any purpose as<br />

legitimate. The decision of the Tenth Circuit in Powers v Harris offers a<br />

powerful illustration of <strong>this</strong> problem. 53 The law in question required any<br />

person who wished to sell caskets to meet a number of stringent criteria<br />

including: completing sixty credit hours of specified undergraduate training; an<br />

52<br />

Price suggests a neat formula for <strong>this</strong> step: ‘A legal rule’s purpose is legitimate, under the<br />

rationality principle, if and only if it is consistent with all other legal and constitutional<br />

constraints, including the Bill of Rights and the Constitution’s “objective, normative value<br />

system”.’ This position will ‘constrain ... judges to deciding only questions of law’ in<br />

Woolman & Bilchitz (n 7 above) 47. As elegant as <strong>this</strong> structure is, I do not think it deals<br />

with the difficulties I identify below. The purpose of a law can be framed at various levels<br />

of abstraction, some of which will be legal while others will not. The structure also has<br />

<strong>this</strong> effect: It incorporates into the rationality test the requirement that the state make<br />

not only laws with constitutional effects, but always act with a constitutional purpose.<br />

The extent to which purpose alone is a valid reason to invalidate a law is controversial in<br />

the US and is largely unexplored in South Africa. Adding it to rationality review probably<br />

causes more problems than it solves. In my view, starting from the point that rational<br />

basis review is meant to prohibit ‘naked preferences’ – keeping in mind the various ways<br />

purpose can be changed – is a better way to approach the problem of legitimacy. This is<br />

perhaps an example of where my focus on equality leads me to a different viewpoint to<br />

that observed through Price’s wider lens.<br />

53 379 F 3d 1208 (10th Cir 2004).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!