04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Does transformative constitutionalism require the recognition of animal rights? 189<br />

as a foundation for the fundamental rights that they proclaimed. 55 The<br />

post-World War II German Constitution also consequently included<br />

human dignity in its very first article and provided that it shall be<br />

‘inviolable’ and that it is the duty of all state authority to respect and protect<br />

it. 56 South African history also saw the denial of the equal dignity of<br />

human beings, with the whole structure of society and governance being<br />

based upon the superiority of whites and the inferiority of black people.<br />

This in turn led to the massive denial of rights in the case of black people<br />

and a range of practices – such as the ‘pass laws’ – that imposed<br />

humiliation and insult upon them. The assertion of equal dignity in the<br />

Constitution represents a repudiation of <strong>this</strong> history and a strong<br />

commitment to ensure that no human being may be subject to such<br />

reprehensible treatment in future. ‘[J]ust as the Germans have promised not<br />

to shovel people into stoves, so too have South Africans promised never<br />

again to treat people like cattle to be packed off to Bantustans or to be<br />

slaughtered in the middle of the night.’ 57 The Constitutional Court has in<br />

several cases confirmed <strong>this</strong> understanding of the meaning and function of<br />

dignity in our constitutional order. Justice O’Regan, for instance, gives<br />

clear expression to <strong>this</strong> idea when she writes that ‘[t]he Constitution asserts<br />

dignity to contradict our past in which human dignity for black South<br />

Africans was routinely and cruelly denied. It asserts it to inform the future,<br />

to invest in our democracy respect for the intrinsic worth of all human<br />

beings.’ 58<br />

In the light of South African history, such a statement is clearly<br />

poignant and of crucial importance. It perhaps represents a further<br />

central principle of the Constitution that human beings should never be<br />

treated again in a manner that fails to respect their dignity. Yet, as we have<br />

seen, that very history mandates a strong ‘equality principle’ in the<br />

interpretation of our Constitution that involves not arbitrarily subjecting<br />

any individual to prejudicial treatment. If we are not to have a normative<br />

conflict at the heart of our Constitution, these two principles must be<br />

reconciled with one another. It will not do simply to ban arbitrary<br />

discrimination amongst human beings for, as has been argued in section 1<br />

above, that would undermine the very insights of the equality principle<br />

55 As Woolman has put it, ‘“dignity” is the flip-side of “never again”’: See ‘Dignity’ in<br />

S Woolman et al Constitutional law of South Africa (2006) 36-4. For <strong>this</strong> reason, he claims<br />

that it is no accident that it plays a central role in German jurisprudence.<br />

56 Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany http://www.iuscomp.org/gla/<br />

statutes/GG.htm#1.<br />

57<br />

Woolman (n 55 above) 36-4.<br />

58 Dawood, Shalabi and Thomas v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 3 SA 936 (CC) para 35.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!