04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Does balancing adequately capture the nature of rights? 277<br />

greater must be the certainty of its underlying premises.’ 43 This principle<br />

would require courts only to accept relatively conclusive evidence on the<br />

basis of which to limit a fundamental right: speculation and weak causal or<br />

evidentiary claims would not be accepted. 44<br />

Alexy’s point here seems to be well-taken and is important for courts to<br />

bear in mind when conducting a proportionality analysis. It is questionable,<br />

however, whether it provides a fully adequate response to the<br />

concerns of theorists such as Kumm and Meyerson: The problems they<br />

fear seem capable of arising in the assessment of the relative weight of<br />

principles in the balancing process even where empirical questions are not<br />

at issue. Importantly, I have sought to argue in <strong>this</strong> section that their critique<br />

of Alexy’s theory does not fundamentally impugn his conceptualisation of<br />

rights or of proportionality; what it does do is place the focus on certain<br />

features of his theory that are both incomplete and pose dangers for the<br />

protection of rights through courts. The logical conclusion would be to<br />

adopt certain procedural safeguards in legal systems using proportionality<br />

analysis that could correct for the under-protection of rights towards which<br />

it may lead. There is also a need to adopt a substantive conception of rights<br />

that links to the structural one. I now turn to consider a critique of Alexy’s<br />

conception of rights that draws out some of the implications of his view to<br />

suggest that far from offering ‘too weak’ a conception of rights, his<br />

understanding of them may be ‘too strong’.<br />

2 Does Alexy’s account of rights render them too strong?<br />

This objection is rooted in Alexy’s conception of rights which, as has been<br />

seen already, he characterises as principles rather than rules. Dworkin<br />

gives a relatively modest account of principles as stating ‘a reason that<br />

argues in one direction, but does not necessitate a particular decision’. 45 He<br />

also contends that an integral part of the concept of a principle is that it has<br />

the dimension of ‘weight’, which gives expression to its importance in any<br />

particular setting. 46 Alexy seeks to build on Dworkin’s account of<br />

principles (and the distinction between them and rules) but goes one step<br />

further in characterising principles as optimisation requirements, norms<br />

that must be fulfilled to the ‘greatest extent possible’. 47<br />

43 Alexy (n 30 above) 342.<br />

44<br />

Justice Ngcobo, writing for the minority, made a remark that indicates his acceptance of<br />

<strong>this</strong> point in Prince v President, Cape Law Society 2002 2 SA 794 (CC) para 74 where he<br />

stated that ‘[i]n my view, a constitutional right cannot be denied on the basis of mere<br />

speculation unsupported by conclusive and convincing evidence’.<br />

45 Dworkin (n 10 above) 26.<br />

46 Dworkin (n 10 above) 27.<br />

47<br />

Alexy (n 6 above) 47. Alexy (in n 27 of ch 3 at 48) notes that he differs from Dworkin on the<br />

characterisation of principles as optimisation requirements.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!