04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Towards a framework for understanding constitutional deference 301<br />

and the less appropriate the matter becomes for judicial resolution. As<br />

Fuller recognised, concealed polycentric elements are probably present in<br />

almost all problems resolved by adjudication ... It is a question of knowing<br />

when the polycentric elements have become so significant and predominant<br />

that the proper limits of adjudication have been reached. 45<br />

This, in turn, will mean that courts tend to be reluctant to become<br />

engaged in matters that they regard as sufficiently polycentric, and will<br />

find them to be non-justiciable. As Fuller notes, however, a high degree of<br />

polycentricity cannot be a bar to judicial resolution in itself, and there may<br />

be instances where it is preferable for a court to engage in the resolution of<br />

a polycentric matter where it cannot be adequately resolved through other<br />

means. 46<br />

In <strong>this</strong> discussion of Fuller’s work, the focus is on three important issues<br />

implicated by the judicial resolution of polycentric disputes – issues which<br />

are relevant for the determination of justiciability and the appropriate level of<br />

deference to be applied by a court in a particular matter. The first issue is the<br />

lack of evidence before, or lack of expertise within, a court to enable it to<br />

predict accurately the consequences of its decisions. 47 Moreover, if parties<br />

who may be adversely affected are not before the court – even if they could be<br />

identified – it may not be practical for a judge to attempt to take all their<br />

interests into account. When a court is confronted with having to decide a<br />

complex, polycentric matter it should therefore, in Allison’s words, avoid<br />

choosing to decide the matter in a way that results in a decision which<br />

‘necessitates an appreciation of complex repercussions’; nor should it develop<br />

the law where a similar appreciation of the repercussions is required. 48 It<br />

will not, however, always be clear to the court whether a matter before it is<br />

one which involves a complex, polycentric determination, precisely because<br />

the evidence before it is limited to that which the parties place before it. For<br />

Allison, Fuller’s concept of polycentricity therefore becomes too vague to<br />

use as a principle of adjudication. 49 Allison also criticises Fuller for failing to<br />

explain what the alternative to judicial resolution of polycentric matters is.<br />

The other social institutions identified by Fuller (the legislature, mediation,<br />

contract, and managerial decision making) are similarly not ideally suited to<br />

deciding polycentric matters – although Fuller does argue that contract and<br />

managerial direction are superior. Neither does Fuller adequately explain<br />

when it would be preferable, as a matter of principle, for courts nevertheless<br />

to engage in polycentric decision-making. 50 Thus, while Fuller’s concept of<br />

45 Fuller (n 39 above) 398.<br />

46<br />

Fuller (n 39 above) 405 - 406. Allison notes that in his correspondence with Frank<br />

Newman, Fuller accepted that in certain situations, decisions such as the desegregation<br />

decisions of the 1950s were necessary, but that they place a ‘serious moral drain on the<br />

integrity of adjudication’: Allison (n 44 above) 374.<br />

47 Fuller (n 39 above) 401.<br />

48 Allison (n 44 above) 370 - 371.<br />

49<br />

Allison (n 44 above) 372 - 373.<br />

50 Fuller (n 39 above) 398 - 400; Allison (n 44 above) 373 - 374.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!