06.04.2013 Views

Johnson 2004 - CDLI - UCLA

Johnson 2004 - CDLI - UCLA

Johnson 2004 - CDLI - UCLA

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

which refer to permanent properties of the referent, are excluded as modifiers of the noun<br />

under the definiteness effect (see below, section 3.5, for a discussion of stage- and<br />

individual-level predicates, topicality and the opposition between adjectival and verbal<br />

small clauses in recent work by Basilico [2003]). Later authors have also identified<br />

definiteness effects in relational “have” sentences and, as noted above, head-internal<br />

relative clauses (see, among numerous other available references, in particular, Davidson<br />

1967; Stowell 1981, 1983; Safir 1985; Reuland and Meulen 1987; Diesing 1992;<br />

Herburger 2000; Jäger 2001, passim non vidi; on the role of indefinites in certain kinds of<br />

complex verb formation, strongly resembling the Sumerian verbal complex, see Szabolcsi<br />

1986; Koopman and Szabolcsi 2000: 32, 222, fn. 2).<br />

Before turning to the exceptions to the definiteness effect, which are really the most<br />

interesting part about it, the precise definition of what an existential “there” sentence in<br />

English is, is in need of some clarification. The most important detail is that it must be<br />

kept separate from presentational “there” sentences.<br />

(42) There is a post office next to the library.<br />

In (42), we have a standard existential “there” sentence: note the indefinite article on the<br />

noun that immediately follows the copula. If the immediately post-copular noun is<br />

definite, “there” and the post-copular noun can alternate on either side of the “to be” verb<br />

without affecting the meaning much at all as in (43) below.<br />

244

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!