06.04.2013 Views

Johnson 2004 - CDLI - UCLA

Johnson 2004 - CDLI - UCLA

Johnson 2004 - CDLI - UCLA

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

public does not need to be inalienably possessed; it simply needs to be “secret”, in<br />

some way.<br />

Pylkkänen cites as evidence the following example in which the perceived object is<br />

decidedly alienable.<br />

(28) Gil ra’a le-Rina et ha-mismaxim<br />

PN saw to-Rina Acc the-documents<br />

Gil saw the documents that Rina had<br />

The requirement for non-public objects of direct perception follows directly from the fact<br />

that “source applicatives . . . always involve an implication of loss, but this loss does not<br />

need to be concrete” (Pylkkänen 2002, 48). It should be relatively clear that the model<br />

that underlies low source applicatives is a transfer of possession model: an object of<br />

possession starts out in the possession of one entity and moves into the possession of<br />

another. Although acts of direct perception are quite abstract, Pylkkänen seems to be<br />

arguing that the perception of an entity initially “belongs” to that entity and the act of<br />

perception transfers the perception from the perceived object to its perceiver as if it were<br />

the referent of a concrete noun. At this point, it may be useful to turn to the first<br />

collection of exemplars from Sumerian, since they can be divided two primary groups,<br />

verbs of perception and affect, as well as third group of exceptions (those involving ßu<br />

“hand” are dealt with in chapter 2).<br />

55

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!