31.07.2015 Views

Steven Pinker -- How the Mind Works - Hampshire High Italian ...

Steven Pinker -- How the Mind Works - Hampshire High Italian ...

Steven Pinker -- How the Mind Works - Hampshire High Italian ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

134 HOW THE MIND WORKS. . . Special consideration is given to a study of consciousness as opposedto unconsciousness, with many helpful hints on how to remain conscious.Verbal humor sets readers up with one meaning of an ambiguous wordand surprises <strong>the</strong>m with ano<strong>the</strong>r. Theoreticians also trade on <strong>the</strong> ambiguityof <strong>the</strong> word consciousness, not as a joke but as a bait-and-switch:<strong>the</strong> reader is led to expect a <strong>the</strong>ory for one sense of <strong>the</strong> word, <strong>the</strong> hardestto explain, and is given a <strong>the</strong>ory for ano<strong>the</strong>r sense, <strong>the</strong> easiest to, explain.I don't like to dwell on definitions, but when it comes to consciousnesswe have no choice but to begin by disentangling <strong>the</strong> meanings.Sometimes "consciousness" is just used as a lofty synonym for "intelligence."Gould, for example, must have been using it in this way. But<strong>the</strong>re are three more-specialized meanings, nicely distinguished by <strong>the</strong>linguist Ray Jackendoff and <strong>the</strong> philosopher Ned Block.One is self-knowledge. Among <strong>the</strong> various people and objects that anintelligent being can have information about is <strong>the</strong> being itself. Not onlycan I feel pain and see red, I can think to myself, "Hey, here I am, Steve<strong>Pinker</strong>, feeling pain and seeing red!" Oddly enough, this recondite senseof <strong>the</strong> word is <strong>the</strong> one that most academic discussions have in mind.Consciousness is typically defined as "building an internal model of <strong>the</strong>world that contains <strong>the</strong> self," "reflecting back on one's own mode ofunderstanding," and o<strong>the</strong>r kinds of navel-gazing that have nothing to dowith consciousness as it is commonly understood: being alive and awakeand aware.Self-knowledge, including <strong>the</strong> ability to use a mirror, is no more mysteriousthan any o<strong>the</strong>r topic in perception and memory. If I have a mentaldatabase for people, what's to prevent it from containing an entry formyself? If I can learn to raise my arm and crane my neck to sight a hiddenspot on my back, why couldn't I learn to raise a mirror and look up atit to sight a hidden spot on my forehead? And access to informationabout <strong>the</strong> self is perfectly easy to model. Any beginning programmer canwrite a short piece of software that examines, reports on, and even modifiesitself. A robot that could recognize itself in a mirror would not bemuch more difficult to build than a robot that could recognize anythingat all. There are, to be sure, good questions to ask about <strong>the</strong> evolution ofself-knowledge, its development in children, and its advantages (and,more interesting, disadvantages, as we shall see in Chapter 6). But selfknowledgeis an everyday topic in cognitive science, not <strong>the</strong> paradox of

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!