31.07.2015 Views

Steven Pinker -- How the Mind Works - Hampshire High Italian ...

Steven Pinker -- How the Mind Works - Hampshire High Italian ...

Steven Pinker -- How the Mind Works - Hampshire High Italian ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Good Ideas 335both"—you get only one of <strong>the</strong>m free; if you want <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, you have topay for it. Far<strong>the</strong>r along, we learn that John chose coffee. From <strong>the</strong>premises "not both free beer and free coffee" and "free coffee," wederive "not free beer" by a logical inference. The answer to question (b)is also no. Our knowledge of restaurants reminds us that food and beveragesare not free unless explicitly offered as such by <strong>the</strong> menu. We<strong>the</strong>refore add <strong>the</strong> conditional "if not steak, <strong>the</strong>n no free red wine." Johnchose <strong>the</strong> soup and salad, which suggests he did not choose steak; weconclude, using a logical inference, that he did not get a free glass ofwine.Logic is indispensable in inferring true things about <strong>the</strong> world frompiecemeal facts acquired from o<strong>the</strong>r people via language or from one'sown generalizations. Why, <strong>the</strong>n, do people seem to flout logic in storiesabout archeologists, biologists, and chess players?One reason is that logical words in everyday languages like Englishare ambiguous, often denoting several formal logical concepts. The Englishword or can sometimes mean <strong>the</strong> logical connective OR (A or B orboth) and can sometimes mean <strong>the</strong> logical connective XOR (exclusive or:A or B but not both). The context often makes it clear which one <strong>the</strong>speaker intended, but in bare puzzles coming out of <strong>the</strong> blue, readerscan make <strong>the</strong> wrong guess.Ano<strong>the</strong>r reason is that logical inferences cannot be drawn out willynilly.Any true statement can spawn an infinite number of true but uselessnew ones. From "Iowa grows soybeans," we can derive "Iowa growssoybeans or <strong>the</strong> cow jumped over <strong>the</strong> moon," "Iowa grows soybeans andei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> cow jumped over <strong>the</strong> moon or it didn't," ad infinitum. (This isan example of <strong>the</strong> "frame problem" introduced in Chapter 1.) Unless ithas all <strong>the</strong> time in <strong>the</strong> world, even <strong>the</strong> best logical inferencer has to guesswhich implications to explore and which are likely to be blind alleys.Some rules have to be inhibited, so valid inferences will inevitably bemissed. The guessing can't itself come from logic; generally it comesfrom assuming that <strong>the</strong> speaker is a cooperative conversational partnerconveying relevant information and not, say, a hostile lawyer or a toughgradinglogic professor trying to trip one up.Perhaps <strong>the</strong> most important impediment is that mental logic is not ahand-held calculator ready to accept any As and B's and C's as input. Itis enmeshed with our system of knowledge about <strong>the</strong> world. A particularstep of mental logic, once set into motion, does not depend on worldknowledge, but its inputs and outputs are piped directly into that knowl-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!