28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Preface<br />

This dissertation examines a neglected area of Leibniz’s philosophy, namely, his<br />

theory of right (jus). Contrary to prevailing views, I argue that his theory, much of which<br />

is established in his earliest writings, is the foundation of his practical philosophy as a<br />

whole. In contemporary terms, Leibniz’s conception of right may be called “subjective<br />

right,” rooted in the Grotian tradition; but it is also informed by a variety of historical<br />

sources, most dominantly Aristotle and Roman Law. In general, we can understand<br />

Leibniz’s theory to be motivated by two main concerns: (1) to establish the moral<br />

limitations on power, whether natural, political, or divine power; (2) to reconcile utilitas<br />

(conceived as the good for oneself) with honestas (conceived as the good for others). The<br />

resolution to these concerns, I argue, lies in Leibniz’s a priori “science” of right.<br />

A key feature of this science is Leibniz’s demonstrative method, which consists of<br />

the analysis of definitions and the derivation of precepts. I show, according to Leibniz’s<br />

definitions, that the science of right is constructed in the following way: right (jus) and<br />

obligation are the moral qualities of a rational substance (substantia rationalis). In other<br />

words, right is the moral power (potentia moralis) and obligation is the moral necessity<br />

of a person to perform and to demand what is just. On this deontic basis Leibniz<br />

“derives” additional founding principles: the three precepts of right (harm no one, give to<br />

each his due, and live honorably); the just condition (the common good); the definition of<br />

the good person (one who loves everyone); and justice defined as a virtue (ultimately as<br />

“the charity of the wise”). Thus, the concepts of right and obligation denote the deontic<br />

moral properties of an agent enabling her to act according to an objectively just order. On<br />

the most basic level, subjective right is the self-limiting, self-determining, capacity of a<br />

moral agent. On the broadest level subjective right implies moral perfection or virtue, and<br />

partly constitutes the freedom of rational beings. While Leibniz’s practical philosophy<br />

undergoes certain developments, this foundation of right as a moral power remains<br />

essential. Notably, Leibniz had established this foundation well-before his earliest<br />

conception of monadic substance.<br />

Most treatments of Leibniz’s practical philosophy focus on the requirements of<br />

pleasure, happiness, love, divine retribution, metaphysical perfection, or on the<br />

compatibility of divine free will with divine creation of an optimum world. Most<br />

commentators hold that Leibniz’s theory of right (often subsumed under the more general<br />

category of “natural law”) derives from these central and overarching metaphysical<br />

premises, or, that his early formulations are superseded and sufficiently summarized by<br />

his mature definition of justice as “charity of the wise” (caritas sapientis). However, I<br />

argue that the derivation is exactly reversed: these central metaphysical premises, along<br />

with caritas sapientis, depend on his science of right as their normative foundation.<br />

This reversal of ground and consequent in Leibniz’s practical philosophy requires<br />

understanding the logical connection between the moral qualities (right and obligation)<br />

and the precepts of right. It also requires carefully distinguishing the meanings of right<br />

(jus), just (justum) and justice (justitia) as a virtue. Furthermore, Leibniz’s attempt to<br />

reconcile utilitas and honestas leads him to find “disinterested love” essential to justice,<br />

and this appears to lead him to fundamentally hedonist grounds for practical philosophy. I

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!