28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

above, “the right of peace rules so long as one does not instigate a war.” Hobbes does not<br />

have the “two-fold quality” that makes right imply an obligation. For Leibniz, natural<br />

right is not a power simpliciter, but a moral power, which means the power not to violate<br />

the right of another. Furthermore, on the level of strict right, each person is regarded<br />

equally, not by virtue of an equal capacity to overpower another, but by the moral<br />

capacity each person has to maintain peaceful coexistence. 102 Therefore, the precept of<br />

strict right, based on the moral qualities, distinguishes Leibniz from Hobbes.<br />

This difference is further made here by Leibniz’s discussion of our power over<br />

things, that is, our power of acquiring and possessing them. While the right and<br />

obligation of peaceful coexistence holds among rational persons, the right of war<br />

characterizes our relations with respect to things (or non-persons). As he says, just as a<br />

lion is permitted (licet) to destroy a man, and an avalanche to crush him, men are<br />

permitted to restrain the lion, and to mine the mountain. Thus we have a right to<br />

possession through capturing and conquering things, and the right of war to keep them, as<br />

long as they are not already possessed by other persons. 103 Leibniz is clear that taking<br />

another’s rightfully acquired possessions gives the right of war to the other, and that<br />

stealing constitutes a violation of the precept against harm. 104 To lie is also a harm, a<br />

harm to the mind; and from this stems the requirement (necessitas) to keep promises.<br />

Offenses then are covered under the precept of strict right: “harm no one, so that the right<br />

of war may not be given.” 105 It may be said that Leibniz thus follows Grotius and earlier<br />

rights theorists who maintained that subjective right is a power permitting one (or<br />

authorizing one) to acquire, control, and maintain property.<br />

Leibniz concludes the section on “strict right” by mentioning two important<br />

Aristotelian terms that he does not explain here. He says that the precept against harm<br />

“pertains to Commutative justice, and to [the] Right, which Grotius calls faculty.” 106<br />

These terms, ‘commutative’ and ‘faculty,’ are used differently by different authors, and<br />

Leibniz uses them as short hand in later texts. So, it is important to have some sense of<br />

what he means by them. I will first discuss ‘commutative’ and then ‘faculty.’ In<br />

Nicomachean Ethics (Bk. V chap. 3-4), Aristotle discusses two kinds of justice: (1)<br />

distributive and (2) commutative. As for (1) he defines ‘the just’ as a proportion in which<br />

goods are distributed according to merit. For example, “the common funds of a<br />

partnership [will be distributed] according to the same ratio which the funds put into the<br />

business by the partners bear to one another.” 107 Thus, when goods are distributed in<br />

102<br />

This will be shown in the second degree of right. Leibniz will claim that we naturally seek not merely<br />

peaceful coexistence, but also the improvement of society as a whole. Thus the precept against harm is a<br />

negative right, since it commands us to refrain from doing wrong, but the second precept (give each his<br />

due) commands us to act benevolently and is thus a positive right.<br />

103<br />

A.6.1.343.§73: “Victoria autem personae super rem reique captivitas dicitur possessio. Possessio igitur<br />

dat personae Jus in rem, Jure belli, dummodo res sit nullius.”<br />

104<br />

A.6.1.343.§73: “Si igitur alterum alter vel in persona, vel rebus suis laesit, dat ei Jus quod habet in rem<br />

seu Jus belli.”<br />

105<br />

A.6.1.343.§73: “Est autem et inter laesionis species deceptio perniciosa, qua damnum datur menti, ex<br />

quo descendit servandorum promissorum necessitas. Ex quo patet Juris Naturae meri unicum praeceptum<br />

esse: Neminem laedere, ne detur ei Jus belli.”<br />

106<br />

A.6.1.343.§73: “Huc pertinet Justitia Commutativa, et Jus, quod Grotius vocat Facultatem.”<br />

107<br />

AE 1131b29-31. So, for example, if partner A had put in 50 drachmas to start the olive business, while<br />

partner B had put in 100 drachmas, A would get 34% of the profits, while B would get 66%. This is not<br />

Aristotle’s example, but it illustrates the point.<br />

28

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!