28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

what is not unjust—to do what you will when no issue is involved. Right<br />

is the power of doing what is just. (LL 137) 111<br />

Let us take these propositions one by one. The definition of justice is repeated here,<br />

except that it contains not only the habit of doing, but of expecting. Perhaps this is<br />

because virtue consists partly in a state of readiness to perform just acts, rather than in a<br />

passive state. We can also assume that justice is the virtue of being just. However, the<br />

just has not been clearly defined in the investigation, except negatively. The epagogic<br />

induction rejected every proposed definition of the just, without clearly indicating any<br />

acceptable ones. So, how do we define it? There are several indications: First, here it<br />

appears to be synonymous with the permissible, although this is unhelpfully defined as<br />

whatever is not unjust. Yet this appears to refer to acts of choice that affect no one, such<br />

as, say, when I eat an apple that belongs to me. Secondly, it seems that the just can be<br />

defined positively after all, as equity or the equitable (aeqvum). Leibniz had spent<br />

considerable effort in Draft 2 attempting to define the just in terms of an equitable<br />

proportion of good. As we have also seen, ‘equity’ names the second degree of natural<br />

right, whose precept is “give to each his due.” It is fair to say then that the just and equity<br />

are coextensive. Furthermore, equitable is defined in the above paragraph as “loving<br />

everyone whenever an occasion arises.” This certainly defines the just in a positive sense.<br />

In addition, this definition actually expands the scope of the just, to include not merely<br />

loving one other, but loving every other. So, then, it is just to love everyone. What<br />

remains undetermined here is this rather vague expression, “whenever an occasion<br />

arises.” This may refer to the occasions referred to above, such as when another needs<br />

help and we can provide it, or when we can provide the good for another at no loss to<br />

ourselves. I suggest that these occasions will be better specified by the arguments for the<br />

Golden Rule and the three degrees of natural right Leibniz develops later (see Chapter<br />

Six).<br />

Another way to define the just is in terms of Condition A, the means-end<br />

condition. Leibniz rejects the idea that it is just to act from the motive of reward and<br />

punishment, since this may result in using another as a means to one’s own ends.<br />

Therefore, the opposite will be just—i.e., not to use others for one’s own ends. This may<br />

appear to be a negative rather than positive determination (it does not tell us what is<br />

permissible, but only what is impermissible). However, it could just as well be rendered<br />

positively as, “it is just to promote the ends of others for the other’s own sake.” And this<br />

is exactly what it means to love them. Thus I think we can conclude from this paragraph,<br />

and thus from the investigation of the terms, that the just means to love everyone, without<br />

harm to oneself.<br />

The following proposition, however, is quite puzzling. In what sense are we<br />

obligated, or indebted, to do that which is equitable, i.e., to love everyone? In one sense,<br />

obligation itself, as we have seen from the Nova Methodus, stems from the moral power<br />

111 A.6.1.465: “Est ergo, ut concludamus tandem aliqvando, vera perfectaqve Iustitiae definitio, habitus<br />

amandi alio, seu capiendi voluptatem ex opinione boni alieni qvoties qvaestio incidit. Aeqvum est amare<br />

alios omnes qvoties qvaestio incidit. Obligati sumus (debemus) ad id (id) qvod aeqvum est. Injustum est<br />

bono alieno non delectari qvoties qvaestio incidit. Iustum (Licitum) est, qvicqvid injustum non est. Iustum<br />

ergo est non tantum qvod aeqvum est, ut delectari bono alieno, cum qvaestio incidit, sed qvod non injustum<br />

est, uti facere qvidis, qvoties non incidit. Ius est potentia agendi qvod justum est. ”<br />

74

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!