28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

love are both morally acceptable and physically possible. Thus (C) the pleasure<br />

conditions fulfills both, since it holds in both A and B. In sum, love makes it possible to<br />

act justly.<br />

Leibniz then immediately turns to the question of justice. And now we can readily<br />

see how Leibniz’s arguments solve the problem in those terms:<br />

Since justice, therefore, demands that we seek the good of others in itself,<br />

and since to seek the good of others in itself is to love them, it follows that<br />

[the nature of justice is love]. (LL 137) 106<br />

Leibniz has thus solved the Carneadean problem of justice. Justice is compatible with<br />

one’s own and another’s good, since both goods involve love. And since to love another<br />

provides the required motive, it is possible to act justly. As long as we modify the claim<br />

about pleasure, by saying that pleasure is the result or accompaniment of an action, then<br />

Leibniz’s argument is fairly coherent.<br />

1. Justice is the compatibility of one’s own good with another’s (problem to be<br />

solved).<br />

2. Love is the per se good for oneself (pleasure).<br />

3. Love is the per se good for another (pleasure).<br />

4. No action can be taken except for the pleasure found in it.<br />

5. Since acts of love result in mutual pleasure, acts of love are motivationally<br />

possible.<br />

6. Since the compatibility of goods is possible only through love, therefore, the<br />

nature of justice is love.<br />

This argument involving the definitions of pleasure and love refutes Carneades<br />

skepticism about justice. Since the nature of justice is love, and love means to find<br />

pleasure in the happiness of another, both self and other are accommodated in justice. In<br />

other words, there is justice (as everyone agrees) and it is not folly.<br />

It is important to notice that the argument is made to fulfill the demand that is set<br />

out in the beginning, as if to say: ‘intuitively, the condition that justice must fulfill is the<br />

compatibility of goods. Now let us find a way to fulfill the condition.’ It is the condition<br />

of justice, defined as the compatibility between one’s own good and another’s that<br />

generates the solution, namely, the motive of love. Love is not, however, the condition to<br />

be fulfilled from the beginning. Rather, we are obligated to be just—and this is possible<br />

only through love. Additionally, if his arguments appear to make him a hedonist, that is<br />

because on a certain level he is. But we should not oversimplify the matter. Leibniz does<br />

not think that pleasure alone is sufficient for the highest goods (virtue and happiness). 107<br />

Moreover, he recognizes that some pleasures are not good to have, such as when they can<br />

lead to harm, or in case we find pleasure in evil actions. Simply put Leibniz just thinks<br />

that pleasure solves the motivational problem. Pleasure is the good that we find in doing<br />

just acts, and love fulfills the condition, by being defined as seeking the pleasure of<br />

106 A.6.1.465: “Cum ergo bonum alienum justitia exigat per se expeti, cum per se expeti bonum alienum, sit<br />

alios amari, seqvitur de natura justitiae esse amorem.”<br />

107 I will discuss these “highest goods” in Chapter Six.<br />

72

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!