28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Leibniz also says that what is true for speculative principles is also true for<br />

practical principles: “As I have already pointed out; the finest moral precepts and the best<br />

prudential rules in the world have weight only in a soul which is as sensitive to them as to<br />

what opposes them” (NE 2.21.35). This means, as he explains, that when we prefer<br />

something less good than what the intellect tells us is a higher-degree good, it is because<br />

the ideas in the intellect lacks sufficient sensitivity to be noticed and effective. Thus, to<br />

insure that we follow the truly good requires that we to train ourselves to maintain images<br />

pertaining to the good. 90 And this begins to get us to the third point. Since both abstract<br />

thought and practical principles require imagination, and imagination is a function of our<br />

sensibility, then the intelligible truths of morality require “fleshing out,” so to speak. That<br />

is to say, practical principles must become sensitized by being practiced.<br />

Despite the obscuring effect of sensual inclinations and the motivational weakness<br />

of rational principles, Leibniz does not tell us to eliminate inclinations and passions, but<br />

rather to make intelligible ideas more sensual and thus to make them the principles of<br />

action. In response to Locke, who had concluded that innate principles do not exist<br />

because we continually act against what we know to be right, Leibniz replies that we tend<br />

to turn our thoughts aside from the good because “the future and reasoning seldom strike<br />

as forcefully as do the present and the senses” (NE 1.2.11). This implies that certain<br />

acquired inclinations may be misguided, but also implies that the motives of reason are<br />

too weak to overcome those inclinations. Thus, for a practical principle to be an effective<br />

motive, it must have sensual content. Conversely, the more distinctly a sensation is<br />

perceived in the mind, the more effectively the mind can sort out its particular causes,<br />

effects, and meaning. And this brings us to the third point, to see how Leibniz thought<br />

that virtues could be developed to incorporate the principles of instinct and reason.<br />

As we have seen, Leibniz indicates that both instinct and reason are insufficient<br />

moral motives. But an important element of his practical philosophy is the role he assigns<br />

to virtue as a remedy for these insufficiencies. One example is especially relevant, since it<br />

occurs during the discussion of innate practical principles. Locke criticizes the idea of<br />

virtue, since ultimately it can tell us nothing definitive or useful. He argues that if innate<br />

principles exist, then we should be able to produce a catalog of them. Such a catalog,<br />

Locke notes, had been attempted by Lord Herbert, who includes Virtutem cum pietate<br />

conjunctam optimam esse rationem cultûs divini among his list of innate principles (E<br />

1.2.15). 91 Locke then argues that the meaning of ‘virtue’ is ambiguous between (a) what<br />

some community considers praiseworthy, and (b) an action conformable to God’s will. If<br />

‘virtue’ means (a), then virtue will be so variable that it cannot be said to be innate, and if<br />

(b), virtue will “amount to no more than that God is pleased with the doing of what he<br />

commands”; and while this may be true, it does not tell us “what it is that God doth<br />

command” (E 1.2.18). Therefore, Herbert’s principle of virtue is useless. Leibniz<br />

responds, characteristically, by asserting that while the word ‘virtue’ may be relative in<br />

its application, its general notion is universally agreed upon. He points out that the<br />

Aristotelian definition of virtue is “a general disposition to moderate the passions by<br />

means of reason, or more simply still a disposition to act in accordance with reason” (NE<br />

1.2.19). Under this definition, virtue does not form part of the meaning of a moral<br />

90 Leibniz speaks of these things in Book 2, Chapter 21, “On Power and Freedom.”<br />

91 “Virtue joined with piety is the best worship” (NE 1.2.15). Pehaps more accurate would be: “Virtue<br />

joined with piety is the best account of worship of the divine.”<br />

200

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!