28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

these distinctions in demonstrations. To this end, we should note the following passage<br />

from, “Specimen Inventorum de Admirandis Naturae Generalis Arcanis” (c. 1698).<br />

There is an essential distinction between necessary or eternal truths, and<br />

truths of fact or contingent truths; they differ from one another very much<br />

in the way that rational numbers and surds differ. For necessary truths can<br />

be reduced to identical truths, just as commensurable quantities can be<br />

reduced to a common measure; but in the case of contingent truths, as in<br />

the case of surds, the reduction proceeds to infinity and is never<br />

terminated. So the certitude and perfect reason of contingent truths is<br />

known only to God, who grasps the infinite with one intuition. (PM 75) 12<br />

What this passage shows is that the distinction between necessary and contingent truths<br />

depends on termination of analysis. The analysis of necessary truths terminates in an<br />

identity, while the analysis of contingent truths does not terminate. However, a couple of<br />

problems with this account should be noted. It seems difficult to understand how a<br />

proposition whose reduction is never terminated could be grasped as a whole by any<br />

knower, including God. Leibniz thinks we can understand this by analogy with<br />

mathematical surds, such as pi. The ratio of the circumference to the diameter is fixed by<br />

the size of the circle. So, while the ratio is determinable with certainty, the numerical<br />

expression of this ratio never terminates. Still, we must suppose that, if there is a<br />

sufficient reason for the contingent truth, the analysis must terminate somehow. 13<br />

Another problem is that the distinction appears to rest on degrees of knowledge; that is,<br />

necessary truths are those of which we can be certain, while contingent truths are those of<br />

entails the necessitation of God’s “choice.” Supposedly, God chooses according to some criteria of<br />

compossibility; for example, the greatest variety of things compatible with the greatest order (Monadology<br />

sec. 58); or, according to the laws of minima and maxima (De rerum originatione radicali GP VII 303).<br />

However it is that God determines the choice, it is said to be the best choice within certain required<br />

parameters. It were possible that Caesar crossed the Rubicon; but God made this possibility an actuality by<br />

making it a fact in the existent world. But God’s decision is said to depend on reasons which incline but do<br />

not necessitate (Theodicy, in passim). That is, God’s decision is always determined by a reason, but not<br />

determined by logical necessity. It would be a moral imperfection to choose otherwise, but not a logical<br />

contradiction. Therefore, contingent truths depend on God’s choice, whereas necessary truths do not<br />

depend on God’s choice. According to Leibniz, God could have made the world otherwise—although<br />

commentators dispute whether Leibniz can consistently make this claim. However, a claim which is not<br />

disputed by commentators is that God could not have made necessary truths otherwise.<br />

12 G.7.309: “Essentiale est discrimen inter Veritates necessarias sive aeternas, et veritates facti sive<br />

contingentes, differuntque inter se propemodum ut numeri rationales et surdi. Nam veritates necessariae<br />

resolvi possunt in identicas, ut quantitates commensurabiles in communem mensuram, sed in veritatibus<br />

contingentibus, ut in numeris surdis, resolutio procedit in infinitum, nec unquam terminatur; itaque<br />

certitudo et perfecta ratio veritatum contingentium soli DEO nota est, qui infinitum uno intuitu<br />

complectitur.”<br />

13 Leibniz also thinks that in this way he avoids both necessity and arbitrariness regarding God’s “decision”<br />

to create this world: for any contingent proposition there are reasons which incline God, in the way that a<br />

surd inclines to its resolution, without necessitating God to make a contingent proposition true. But neither<br />

is the reason arbitrary, since a reason can always be given for the decision. However, this argument by<br />

analogy with surds arguably does not prevent God’s choice from being logically necessitated. As Kenneth<br />

Seeskin claims, at some point a decision must be made; and deferring the reason endlessly would mean that<br />

the decision has no sufficient reason. Therefore, the “infinite analysis” argument for God’s freedom is<br />

faulty. See “Moral Necessity” in Leibniz: Critical Assessments.<br />

143

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!