28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

about it, or whether it is a valid distinction to make. 3 For it seems that God has no choice<br />

but to obey the principles of wisdom and goodness; and if so, there is no sense is talking<br />

about God’s freedom as distinct from logical necessity, because God cannot do otherwise<br />

in either case. The only thing that is clear about Leibniz’s distinction is that Leibniz<br />

sought to maintain it.<br />

My purpose in this chapter is not to determine whether Leibniz’s distinction is<br />

valid or whether it solves the dilemma involving God’s freedom. An overabundance of<br />

work has already been done on this topic. Rather, I wish to determine the relationship<br />

between his early and late uses of the term ‘moral necessity.’ This relationship is rarely<br />

discussed among commentators, and when it is, the early usage is dismissed as irrelevant<br />

to the later, consigned to the specific context of his early writings on jurisprudence. 4 Yet<br />

as I have shown throughout this dissertation, it is a mistake to cut off these writings,<br />

especially the earliest ones, from the rest of his practical philosophy, let alone from his<br />

metaphysics in general. My general purpose in this chapter, then, is to show why this<br />

relationship must be taken seriously.<br />

As we saw in Nova Methodus (1667), Leibniz originally defines moral necessity<br />

as obligation, as one of the moral qualities: “thus, moral power is called Right, and moral<br />

necessity is called Obligation.” 5 In the Elementa Juris Naturalis (1671) right and<br />

obligation become the moral qualities of the vir bonus (the good person). 6 The good<br />

person is then defined as “one who loves everyone.” The question is whether there is any<br />

relevant conceptual similarity or relation between the early and late employments of<br />

‘moral necessity.’ In what follows I will show that from early to late ‘moral necessity’<br />

refers to the obligation a rational agent has to perform the moral good. This obligation<br />

has its source in the agent’s very essence, that is, in its moral qualities of right (jus) and<br />

obligation. Furthermore, we can understand that part of what constitutes the agent’s jus is<br />

its wisdom and goodness. Furthermore, understanding this relationship between early and<br />

late uses of moral necessity makes Leibniz’s argument for God’s freedom more clear:<br />

Freedom consists in being morally necessitated, i.e., necessitated by one’s own rationalmoral<br />

essence. We thus understand that human freedom consists in determining ourselves<br />

by the virtue we have in part, but which we are capable of acquiring. Moral necessity will<br />

be understood to be derived from potential moralis, as are the metaphysical requirements<br />

of the best possible world.<br />

These are bold claims. To understand what is at stake in them I begin with some<br />

recent commentary. In his article, “Pre-Leibnizian Moral Necessity,” (2004) Michael J.<br />

Murray claims that the early (1667) and late (1702) uses of “moral necessity” are<br />

conceptually distinct. He claims that the early texts employ moral necessity in “strictly<br />

deontic contexts” (such as those I have just cited above); and so these specifically<br />

“ethical” or “deontic” uses are conceptually distinct from the “action-theoretic” uses in<br />

Theodicy and after:<br />

3 The reader may consult any number of books and articles on this topic, especially R.M. Adams (1994).<br />

4 A perfect example of this view may be found in R.M. Adams, “Moral Necessity” (2005). Another<br />

example will be discussed, below. In his Leibniz, zur Einfürung (2005, p. 186), Hans Poser calls this type<br />

of necessity “ethical necessity” (ethische notwendigkeit) to be distinguished from the moral necessity used<br />

in the context of divine freedom.<br />

5 A.6.1.301.§14: “ita potentia moralis dicitur Jus, necessitas moralis dicitur Obligatio.”<br />

6 A.6.1.465: “Ius est potentia: Obligatio necessitas: viri boni, qvas Grotius vocat Qvalitates Morales, nihil<br />

sunt aliud qvam qvalitates viri boni.”<br />

244

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!