28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

In the science of [right], rather, it is best to derive human justice, as from a<br />

spring, from the divine, to make it complete. Surely the [notion] of the<br />

just, no less than that of the true and the good, relates to God, and above<br />

all to God, who is the measure of all things. And the rules which are<br />

common certainly enter into the science, and ought to be considered in<br />

universal jurisprudence, whose precepts natural theology will use as well<br />

(RP 69). 14<br />

This passage reflects three important and long-standing claims of Leibniz: (a) his view in<br />

the Nova Methodus that “natural theology is a species of jurisprudence, universally<br />

taken.” That is, jurisprudence is the science of the rule of a universal monarch, i.e., God<br />

. 15 (b) Natural theology and natural right share the “common notions” that he speaks of in<br />

the Meditation, as we will see below. (c) In the above two passages, Leibniz speaks of the<br />

sources (capita) of natural right and the spring (fonte) of divine justice. These are two<br />

essential principles. 16 Natural right is the source of the precepts of right, while divine<br />

justice is synonymous with the charity of the wise. This way Leibniz’s ultimate definition<br />

of justice as charity of the wise can be considered the complete definition of natural right.<br />

The object of natural right is, in short, the virtue of justice.<br />

(3) Having outlined the end and object of natural right, Leibniz at last deals with<br />

the efficient cause of natural right and brings to bear his most provocative and influential<br />

criticism of Pufendorf’s voluntarism. 17 It may seem unusual to speak of an efficient cause<br />

of natural right, but this refers to the cause of the sense of obligation in the mind of a<br />

person. Now, Pufendorf does not speak of efficient causes in relation to obligation. 18 He<br />

does however discuss various causes of human actions, e.g., as arising from inclinations<br />

and from the will. For Pufendorf the question is, how does an obligation constrain the<br />

will to act according to a law (lex)? His answer is, by the command of a superior. But<br />

Leibniz finds Pufendorf’s account incoherent.<br />

To begin with Leibniz criticizes Pufendorf for having mistakenly grounded the<br />

efficient cause of natural right in the decree of a superior, rather than where they ought to<br />

be grounded—in the divine understanding.<br />

It now remains to treat the efficient cause of natural right, which our<br />

author does not correctly establish. He, indeed, does not find it in the<br />

14 D 278: “Quin potius in scientia juris a divina justitia, tanquam fonte, humanam, ut plena fit, derivari<br />

convenit. Notio certe justi non minus, quam veri ac boni etiam ad Deum pertinet, immo ad Deum magis,<br />

tanquam mensuram ceterorum, communesque regulae utique in scientiam cadunt, & in jurisprudentia<br />

universali tradi debent, cujus praeceptis etiam theologia naturalis utetur.<br />

15 A.6.1.294.§5 “Nec mirum est, quod in Jurisprudentia, idem et in Theologia usu venire, quia Theologia<br />

species quaedam est Jurisprudientiae universim sumtae, agit enim de Jure et Legibus obtinentibus in<br />

Republica aut potius regno DEI super homines;”<br />

16 In a paper of 1678 (A.6.4.2809) Leibniz outlines the following: “Juris Naturalis Principia et Derivata.<br />

Principia Fons et Capita. Fons: Caritas Sapientis. Capita, jus strictum, aequitas, probitas, quae continentur<br />

praeceptis: neminem laedere, suum cuique tribuere, honeste vivere.” He then does the derivation of Caritas<br />

Sapientis, beginning with “Sapientia est Scientia felicitatis . . . Laetitia . . . Voluptas . . .” etc.<br />

17 See Schneewind (1996) and Hochstrasser (2000 p. 79).<br />

18 Pufendorf’s discussion of obligation is found in Book 1 Chapter 2 of De Officio Hominis et Civis juxta<br />

Legem Naturalem libri duo, the chapter that Leibniz comments on, as seen below.<br />

207

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!