28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

and penalties” but rather are able “to enjoy felicity as a necessary corollary to virtue.”<br />

Thus the wise love God and act honorably toward others because they know that God has<br />

made virtue is its own reward.<br />

This, I think, is Leibniz’s most consistent position, if not his more frequent one.<br />

However, this position is not without problems. First, it makes the other motives morally<br />

superfluous. If virtue is its own reward, then the other motives ought to be either<br />

unnecessary for acting virtuously or insufficiently virtuous. The motives of punishment<br />

and reward only provide incentives for the insufficiently virtuous, but they are not the<br />

motives by which we ought to act. Leibniz implies that one ought to act with honor<br />

because it is right. One ought to have the virtue of justice because it is just. But his<br />

account of motives obscures this fact.<br />

Secondly, it may be objected that the virtuous are still motivated by the pleasure and<br />

happiness they receive from being virtuous; thus, Leibniz cannot really avoid basing the<br />

three precepts on self-love and hedonist motives. There is actually a lot at stake in this<br />

objection. But whether it holds depends on the cogency of Leibniz’s argument for noncalculating<br />

(or disinterested) love. As we saw in the Elementa, to love is to find pleasure<br />

in the happiness of another. This sort of love is honorable, as long as it is done for<br />

another’s sake and not solely for one’s own. This argument may not be convincing. To<br />

make it work it must maintain that gaining pleasure is not the end of action, but virtue is,<br />

and pleasure accompanies this virtue. If we do not find pleasure in acts of virtue, this<br />

does not mean that we have acted wrongly; it means rather that we have not acquired the<br />

right disposition. The right disposition is to find pleasure in virtue, so that virtue may be<br />

done well.<br />

It must also be asked, what, really is honor, for Leibniz? He does not analyze this<br />

concept, even so it is one of his most important. Elsewhere however he does offer at least<br />

one definition of it, one which interestingly resonates with his definition of right.<br />

Truly indeed the honorable is that which we are. It is our mind (the mind<br />

indeed is what most chiefly perfects us). However, perfection of the mind<br />

is the power (potentia) of one in regard to the affects and motions of the<br />

body, which if we are able to restrain sufficiently, nothing may prohibit us<br />

from following reason, which means to cultivate virtue. 53<br />

As rational substances (minds) we have the capacity or power to follow reason, to<br />

cultivate virtue. To be honorable is to act according to that virtue which restrains the<br />

passions and follows reason. This is very much a stoic formulation, but it resonates very<br />

well with the capacity we have (the moral power and obligation) to follow right reason.<br />

More specifically, to live honorably means not to use others for one’s own ends; it means<br />

to tell the truth, to keep promises, and to do good for others, as long as these acts are done<br />

for the sake of others. Indeed, the objective of honor is not only the perfection of oneself<br />

but the perfection of society. Respecting God is supposed to incite us to perform<br />

honorable acts, but it is not really necessary to love God in order to act honorably. What<br />

53 TI: “Vere enim honestum est quicquid nos, id est animum nostrum (animus enim potissimum est id quod<br />

sumus perficit. Perfectio autem animi est potentia eius in corporis affectus motusque, quos si satis<br />

compescere possimus, nihil est quod nos prohibeat rationem sequi id est virtutem colere” (p. 620). This<br />

passage is from a piece titled “De Jure et Justitia” dated 1677-78.<br />

119

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!