28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

another.<br />

Leibniz’s “epagogic” induction is practically complete. After having investigated<br />

the terms right, just, and justice from many angles, he has “induced” that love is the<br />

nature of justice. He does not claim that love is the platonic idea of justice, nor explicitly<br />

that he has deduced the clear and distinct idea of justice. But he shows that the original<br />

intuition concerning justice is explained by love. This marks the permanent “induction,”<br />

in another sense, of the theme of love into Leibniz’s practical philosophy.<br />

Now it remains to formally define justice as a consequence of the induction, as<br />

well as to draw conclusions about the other terms, right and just. The penultimate<br />

paragraph in Draft 4 says the following:<br />

Justice will therefore be the habit of loving others (or seeking the good of<br />

others itself and of taking delight in the good of others), as long as this can<br />

be done prudently (or as long as this is not a cause of greater pain. (LL<br />

137) 108<br />

Notably, justice is now defined in terms very much like a virtue: the habit of loving<br />

others. This shows that justice not only corresponds with the performance of just acts, but<br />

performing them is to be the result of a mind inclined by the acquired disposition to<br />

perform them, by an internal disposition and intention. Also notable is that Leibniz<br />

qualifies the last remark on prudence by saying, “Yet it may not be pertinent to call in<br />

prudence here, for even one who believes, though foolishly, that the good of others is<br />

unrelated to his own pain is nonetheless obligated to them.” 109 This seems to assert once<br />

again that prudence alone is not a sufficient determination of justice or obligation, and<br />

thus neither is one’s own pleasure or pain. I might believe that it is prudent for me to<br />

avoid helping another out of a jam, but I may still have an obligation to do so, whether<br />

fulfilling it causes me pain or not. To make this work, however, Leibniz is committed to<br />

saying that I must find some pleasure in performing a task that is itself unpleasureable.<br />

This may seem paradoxical; yet he does in fact think that if one does not find pleasure in<br />

just acts, then one must be trained to find it. 110<br />

In the final paragraph Leibniz offers a summary of the conclusions to his whole<br />

investigation; but this will require some sorting out.<br />

To reach a conclusion at last, the true and perfect definition of justice is<br />

therefore the habit of loving others, or of finding joy in the expectation of<br />

the good of others, whenever an occasion arises. It is equitable to love<br />

everyone else whenever an occasion arises. We are obligated (we ought)<br />

to do that which is equitable. It is unjust not to be delighted in the good of<br />

others [whenever an occasion arises to be just]. The just (the permissible)<br />

is whatever is not unjust. Therefore the just is not merely what is<br />

equitable—to delight in the good of others when the issue arises—but also<br />

108 A.6.1.465: “Iustitia ergo erit habitus amandi alios (seu per se expetendi bonum alienum, bono alieno<br />

delectandi) qvousqve per prudentiam fieri potest (seu qvousqve majoris doloris causa non est).”<br />

109 A.6.1.465: “Qvanqvam non sit e re prudentiam hic advocari, nam etiam qvi stulte, tamen credit, bonum<br />

alienum versari, sine dolore suo, obligatus est tamen.”<br />

110 See Chapter Six.<br />

73

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!