28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

As Leibniz has argued similarly in the past, the rules of justice are demonstrable “in their<br />

full extent and perfection” only under these assumptions. 32 A number of things have been<br />

said to follow from these assumptions (or, from the proofs, as he has also claimed): If<br />

God exists and the soul is immortal, then we can be sure that just actions will eventually<br />

be rewarded with happiness and unjust actions will eventually be punished. Under these<br />

assumptions we can live under a perfectly benevolent monarch whom we would be<br />

pleased to serve. We even ought to find pleasure in serving God, rather than in serving<br />

ourselves. Only the pleasure we find in serving God can bring us to preserve a truly<br />

universal moral community, rather than a community of thieves. In sum, to answer the<br />

question of how the maxims of justice may be known through reason, the answer is this:<br />

through demonstration. To know them through demonstration means to assume God and<br />

immortality, and to draw conclusions that follow from these assumptions. Presumably,<br />

these conclusions would be the maxims of justice themselves, such as “act honorably.”<br />

Thus in this way we establish at least one sense of the claim that “moral doctrine is a<br />

demonstrative science.” The demonstrative ground of moral doctrine lies not in the<br />

maxims of justice themselves, but rather in the assumptions of God and immortality.<br />

Arguably, however, there are deep difficulties with establishing moral doctrine on<br />

these grounds. For one thing, this demonstration does not explain what a just action is. As<br />

Leibniz has made clear in the Elementa and elsewhere, the punishability of an act does<br />

not by itself determine the justice or injustice of an act; and Leibniz never diverges from<br />

this view. God of course would always punish an unjust act, but the ground of an unjust<br />

act lies in the definition of ‘just’ (or in the definition of ‘right’) and in the rules of justice<br />

themselves. Secondly, Leibniz “demonstrates” here only this: there are strong incentives<br />

or motives for acting justly, namely, reward and punishment. Without the motivating<br />

assumptions of God and immortality, a community, indeed a world, would resemble a<br />

community of self-interested and unruly thieves. Although the rules of justice are<br />

“engraved in the soul,” either as primitive rules or as derived rules, they are not effective<br />

unless we assume God and immortality. Leibniz uses here the same passage from Horace<br />

that he used in 1678, when first ascribing motives to the three degrees of right. 33 The<br />

passage suggests that as long as one can escape divine detection, one will do what is<br />

honorable only out of self-interest. In the end, we ought to seek our pleasure in God,<br />

because the greatest pleasure can be found in God, and in the eternal justice God will<br />

provide. This pleasure, joy, or happiness makes us follow the rules of justice more<br />

effectively and honorably. Therefore, “moral doctrine as a demonstrative science,” at<br />

least at this point, is based fundamentally on motivating principles. But again, these<br />

qu’ils en ont, plustost que sur le plaisir qu’ils y devroient prendre, qui est des plus grands lors que Dieu en<br />

est le fondement; ceux-la sont sujets à ressembler un peu à la societé des Bandits. Sit spes fallendi<br />

miscebunt sacra profanis.” (Fn: Horace Epîtres, I, XVI, v.54.)<br />

32 As we saw in the Codex Juris Gentium: “Ut vero universali demonstratione conficiatur, omne honestum<br />

esse utile, et omne turpe damnosum, assumenda est immortalitas animae, et rector universi DEUS. Ita fit ut<br />

omnes in Civitate perfectissima vivere intelligamur, sub Monarcha, qui nec ob sapientiam falli, nec ob<br />

potentiam vitari potest; idemque tam amabilis est, ut felicitas sit tali domino” (A.4.5.63). It is also<br />

interesting to consider this notion of assumption in relation to Kant’s discussion in the Critique of Practical<br />

Reason of God and immortality as theoretical “postulates,” but not demonstrable (part 1, book 2, chapter 2,<br />

title 4).<br />

33 See my Chapter Three on “De Justitia et Jure.”<br />

179

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!