28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

sacrifice our own happiness for the sake of others. Only in this way can we be motivated<br />

to become as virtuous as we ought to be. In this way, honor is useful to others, as Cicero<br />

says, and our own good is not lost.<br />

It might be objected however that if there are already criteria for honor, then all that<br />

divine guarantees offer are motives to do what is required. Thus it superfluous to the<br />

meaning of honor to ground it on demonstrative proofs for the immortality of the soul<br />

and for God’s existence. What appears to be more morally praiseworthy is to have the<br />

virtue of honor, without requiring these motives for it.<br />

There is another aspect to piety in the Codex that is somewhat different, since it does<br />

not appeal to motives but rather to the grounds for certain duties, namely, the duty not to<br />

harm oneself or one’s own property. These duties, since they do not directly concern<br />

others, cannot be prohibited by positive laws. However, they are “still prohibited by<br />

natural [right], that is, by the eternal laws of the divine monarchy, since we owe ourselves<br />

and every thing to God” (RC 174). As God’s creations, we belong to God; thus our duty<br />

is to respect what is essentially his property. Leibniz also claims that duties to ourselves<br />

imply duties to the state: since the state has an interest in the common good; and since the<br />

common good depends on the individual good, we are obligated to the state not to inflict<br />

harm on ourselves. Yet Leibniz thinks this duty rests ultimately on universal (or divine)<br />

justice:<br />

Now if it is of interest to the state, of how much more interest is it to the<br />

universe that no one use badly what is his? So it is from this that the<br />

highest precept [of right] receives its force, which commands us to live<br />

honorably (that is, piously). (RC 174) 113<br />

Leibniz could argue that since one would not want one’s own property destroyed or<br />

abused, one is obliged not abuse God’s property and universal interest. I cannot treat my<br />

body and possessions in a way that God has not and would not. The moral force of this<br />

argument depends of course on the persuasiveness of the idea that God exists.<br />

Leibniz’s discussion of the three degrees ends at this point: “Thus I have treated the<br />

three precepts of [right] or the three degrees of justice, in the most fitting way, and have<br />

indicated the sources of natural [right]” (RC 174). 114 The “sources,” are subjective right<br />

(jus as a moral power) and the definition of justice as charity of the wise. He has<br />

essentially shown that justice is perfected by God’s guarantee of eternal reward and<br />

punishment. While the precepts have been given a decidedly religious cast, they are not at<br />

all dependent on egoistic motives, as other commentators have claimed. The only motives<br />

they depend on are the assumptions of immortality and God’s existence. But these are<br />

offered as incentives to act virtuously; they do not define virtue or honor. The virtue of<br />

honor is the highest moral power.<br />

113 A 4.5.63: “Nam ut Reipublicae, ita multo magis Universi interest, ne quis re sua male utatur. Itaque hinc<br />

supremum illud juris praeceptum vim accepit, quod honeste (id est pie) vivere jubet.”<br />

114 A.4.5.63: “Ita tria juris praecepta, tresve justitiae gradus, commodissime explicasse nobis videmur,<br />

fontesque juris naturalis designavisse.”<br />

137

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!