28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

person. 20<br />

Thus if God is going to uphold the name of the good person, then a certain moral<br />

necessity is indeed imposed on God.<br />

Section 3: Late formulations in the correspondence with Clarke<br />

It would be chronologically appropriate to turn to Leibniz’s use of “moral<br />

necessity” in the “action-theoretic” context (as Murray puts it) of Theodicy. However, to<br />

get a much clearer idea of the distinction between moral and metaphysical necessity that<br />

Leibniz makes there, it is best to leap ahead to Leibniz’s correspondence with Clarke<br />

(1716). The following passage, in which Leibniz attributes to Clarke the same confusion<br />

he attributed to Bayle, is especially succinct and illustrative. 21<br />

He [Clarke] seems to play with equivocal terms. There are necessities, which<br />

ought to be admitted. For we must distinguish between an absolute and an<br />

hypothetical necessity. We must also distinguish between a necessity, which takes<br />

place because the opposite implies a contradiction; (which necessity is called<br />

logical, metaphysical, or mathematical;) and a necessity which is moral, whereby,<br />

a wise being chooses the best, and every mind follows the strongest inclination.<br />

(5 th letter, §4 p. 56) 22<br />

It may appear as if Leibniz distinguishes as many as seven kinds of necessity here;<br />

however, there are basically only two types anywhere: absolute and hypothetical, under<br />

which are several species. Under absolute necessity falls logical, metaphysical, and<br />

mathematical necessity. This necessity refers to propositions whose truth value depends<br />

solely on the principles of non-contradiction and identity. Propositions the denial of<br />

which results in a contradiction are necessarily true. Necessary truths are either explicit<br />

identities or are reducible to them. Propositions the denial of which does not entail a<br />

contradiction are contingent or hypothetically necessary propositions. A true hypothetical<br />

proposition expresses actual existence, while one that fails to express actual existence is<br />

false. Actual existence depends on God, who “decides” to make what is hypothetical a<br />

reality. Thus, a truth is morally necessary (hypothetically necessary) just in case God has<br />

decided to make it a reality. God’s decision is said to be based on the criterion of<br />

perfection. 23 It is also important to note that the end of this passage offers a general<br />

explanation for action and moral failure. A mind, any mind, (and correspondingly any<br />

body) always follows the strongest inclination. That is, it follows whatever it has<br />

20 A.6.4.2850: “Itaque jus quod habemus agendi vel non agendi, est potentia quaedam sive libertas moralis.<br />

Obligatio autem est moralis necessitas, illi nimirum imposita, qui viri boni nomen tueri velit.”<br />

21 I use the H.G. Alexander translation.<br />

22 G.7.389: “Il semble aussi, qu’on se joue d’equivoques. Il y a des necessités, qu’il faut admettre. Car il<br />

faut distinguer entre une necessité absolue et une necessité hypothetique. Il faut distinguer aussi entre une<br />

necessité qui a lieu, parce que l’opposé implique contradiction, et laquelle est appellée logique,<br />

metaphysique ou mathematique; et entre une necessité qui est morale, qui fait que le sage choisit le<br />

meilleur, et que tout esprit suit l’inclination la plus grande.”<br />

23 See Rescher (2002) for a very thorough and interesting account of this criterion.<br />

250

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!