28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

one’s possessions), which right may be called simply self-defense. However, these rights<br />

are restricted by the obligation not to violate another’s rights to the same. Since each<br />

subject has these rights by definition, each subject is by definition forbidden to violate the<br />

rights of another. The right to one’s body includes the Faculty to acquire, use, own, or<br />

otherwise control things, but not persons. The right of coercion is the right to punish<br />

another for injury to one’s body or for impeding one’s right to acquire things that belong<br />

to no one (discussed below). All of these rights follow directly from the moral quality of<br />

right and obligation, the moral quality of rational substance. Leibniz does not explain<br />

how these rights follow, but it can be fairly assumed that they follow since they are<br />

required for both the preservation of self and of society. The freedom over one’s body<br />

must also include the freedom to acquire things necessary for its preservation, as well as<br />

the right to defend oneself against injury to one’s body. Furthermore, since a moral power<br />

is the power to do what is consistent with public utility, these rights, which everyone<br />

possesses, must also be consistent with public utility.<br />

In §17 Leibniz shows more specifically how these rights are derived from the<br />

moral quality; in fact, it is shown that moral quality is the source of laws under a civil<br />

contract. To begin the section he says, “The cause of moral quality is nature and action.<br />

Nature is the cause of freedom and faculty, and in another, corresponds to the obligation<br />

not to impede.” 66 Once again, this is an expression of the two-fold quality of right and<br />

obligation, although the emphasis is on the obligation that another person has toward<br />

oneself. But what is meant by ‘cause’ and ‘nature’ here is not entirely clear. Presumably,<br />

Leibniz does not mean that the efficient cause of the moral qualities is material nature;<br />

rather, he means that the reason or source of the moral qualities is the nature of rational<br />

substance. The meaning of ‘action’ is more complex. It means the right of force or<br />

coercion (potestas) in relation to (1) the possession of things, (2) restitution in case of<br />

injury to one’s rights, and (3) the maintenance of rights and obligations under<br />

convention. 67 To paraphrase, (1) I have a material right to possession, first over my own<br />

body, which is the right of liberty. This right to possession of my body also grants me a<br />

right to possess things that belong to no one, which right is called faculty (facultas). This<br />

right gives rise to an obligation in the other not to take what I have rightfully acquired.<br />

(2) If this right is violated, it is called injury, and when I am injured in the pure state of<br />

nature, I have the right of coercive force against the violator. This right may be called<br />

“the right of war.” 68 The right of war is given because injury impedes the rights of<br />

freedom, faculty, and force. Injury in the state of nature harms not just a person, but the<br />

whole community; and so injury is the source of the right to punish offenses. 69 This does<br />

not mean that the state of nature is a state of war, since the right of war is not a right to<br />

everything, but only a coercive right against injury. 70 But it means that injury (the<br />

violation of rights) authorizes self-defense. This authorization is the basis for (3) the right<br />

of convention, in which individuals, through mutual promise and acceptance, transfer the<br />

66<br />

A.6.1.303.§17: “Causa Qualitatis Moralis est Natura et Actio. Natura est causa Libertatis et Facultatis et<br />

correspondentis in alio obligationis de non impediendo.”<br />

67<br />

A.6.1.303.§17: “Actio est causa potestatis in persona agente, ad aliquid faciendum, vel in seipsa, aut<br />

rebus suis patiendum estque vel possessio vel injuria vel conventio.”<br />

68<br />

A.6.1.303.§17: “Injuria in statu mere naturali dat laeso jus libertatis, facultatis potestatisque omnimodae,<br />

seu Jus belli in laedentem societatis ruptorem.”<br />

69<br />

A.6.1.303.§17: “Injuria igitur fons est delictorum et quasi deliktorum.”<br />

70<br />

For Leibniz the state of nature is already a state of community, as it is for Aristotle and Grotius.<br />

20

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!