28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Once again, as was to be shown, duty is not divorced from prudence; there is no<br />

dichotomy between own and other good. This has been shown out of the definition of<br />

right as moral power and obligation as moral necessity. 74<br />

So it can be seen how Leibniz “clarifies” (if not makes distinct) the common<br />

assumption of right, by showing what it implies—the definition of right as moral power<br />

and obligation. This is a highly significant result, since the investigation into the “general<br />

agreement” about Right leads to the themes of pleasure, happiness, and love. But what is<br />

most significant is that these themes are brought in as the explanatory principles of<br />

motivation, but not as grounding principles of right. This should raise a serious question<br />

about interpretations of Leibniz’s practical philosophy that assume that natural right is<br />

grounded in these motivational principles. It must be understood, rather, that Leibniz<br />

introduces pleasure, happiness, and love, not as the grounds of right, but rather as<br />

explanations for how it is possible to do what right requires. That is, they are descriptive<br />

principles of motivation that explain how it is possible to act such that the prescriptive<br />

demands of right may be carried out. The subjective power of right entails permissions<br />

and obligations; but it is up to the metaphysics of pleasure, happiness, love (and<br />

eventually perfection) to figure out how the prescribed duties are to be fulfilled. I will<br />

come back to this point, since it arises within the investigation on justice.<br />

After having established that right entails own and other good, Leibniz turns to<br />

justice: “It remains [for us] to see to what extent there is in justice a basis for considering<br />

the good of others.” 75 In other words, although it has been assumed above, it has not yet<br />

been shown, that the meaning of justice entails another’s good. This is what he now sets<br />

out to do. The following paragraphs, however, do not take up this problem in a direct<br />

manner, but rather pass through a number of points related to what is unjust, to what is<br />

the just, to justice as a virtue, to the nature of love, and then finally to the ultimate<br />

definition of justice, concluding Draft 4. I will follow this order and emphasize the most<br />

important points. 76<br />

First, Leibniz considers a number of “generally agreed claims” in regard to what<br />

is unjust, calling them “causes of complaints” (causa qverelarum). 77 His argument is not<br />

especially consequential, but it serves to show that what is objectionable in unjust acts is<br />

not only the act itself, (i.e., its unjust effects) but the will and intention of the agent. First,<br />

he cites a number of cases in which “all would proclaim that an injury has been done.”<br />

74 This point seems to have been overlooked by previous commentators on this draft of the Elementa<br />

(Mulvaney, Schneiders, Busche, and Brown, for example), who pay more attention to the investigation of<br />

iustum and iustitia. They do not mention that right is part of the investigation, and furthermore, often do not<br />

sort out Leibniz’s distinctions among ius, iustum, and iustitia. Brown (1995) however recognizes that<br />

“implicitly at work in this argument, of course, is the principle that ‘ought’ implies ‘can.’” He also usefully<br />

remarks that “It is against this background [i.e., Grotian appetitus societatis and Hobbesian egoism] that we<br />

must understand the intrusion of a theory of motivation into Leibniz’s theory of obligation” (Brown 417).<br />

However, Brown shows that for Leibniz obligations are grounded in egoistic desire and prudence,<br />

consistent neverthless, with altruism (Brown’s argument is compromised by silently excising Leibniz’s<br />

definition of love from the paragraph on right). But this obscures Leibniz’s argument. The theory of<br />

motivation Leibniz has inserted here is clearly a descriptive supplement to his already established definition<br />

of right. Right is not grounded in these prudential motives, but in the moral nature of rational substance.<br />

75 A.6.1.461: “Superest videamus, qvousqve in justitia boni alieni ratio habeatur.”<br />

76 To understand what he is doing it is important to see how the argument develops.<br />

77 These causa qverelarum are different from the raisons de se plaindre he makes use of in the Meditation<br />

(1703).<br />

63

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!