28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

etween “fact” on one hand and “right” on the other: “Persons and things are terms of<br />

fact, [while] power and obligation are terms of Right.” 31 It is thus the terms of right that<br />

determine the rights belonging to persons and involving things. Hubertus Busche explains<br />

the distinction this way: On one hand there is a quaestio facti and on the other a quaestio<br />

juris. The former asks ‘in whose possession is thing y?’ while the latter asks ‘is thing y in<br />

the possession of person x also the property of person x?’ As Busche puts it, “this latter<br />

question has to do with normative criteria and can only be answered through a deduction<br />

or proof of legality.” 32 For Leibniz, a deduction of legality can begin only with<br />

definitions that are prior to fact, i.e., a priori definitions, not with conditions contingently<br />

determined. Thus, the normative grounds of right are to be based on the definitions of the<br />

terms of Right, i.e., jurisprudence, just, right, obligation, law, and property—as we will<br />

see. We may wonder at this point what is the ontological and epistemological status of<br />

these definitions, that is, what sort of thing are definitions and how do we know that these<br />

are the correct definitions. Leibniz does not discuss that here. However, in the Elementa,<br />

as we will see, he takes definitions to be “real” in a platonic sense and analyzes them<br />

more rigorously. In the Nova Methodus, on the other hand, he seems to think it is<br />

sufficient to set out the intensional content of a term, in which the content does not refer<br />

to any factual or existing conditions. This may be seen in what follows.<br />

Having established this methodological point, Leibniz now sets out an important<br />

series of definitions, beginning with the term ‘jurisprudence.’<br />

Jurisprudence is the science of actions, insofar as they are called just or<br />

unjust. Just and unjust are what is useful or harmful to the public. To the<br />

Public means first to the world, or to God, its Rector, and then to<br />

Humanity, and finally to the State. 33<br />

According to this passage, jurisprudence as a whole is the science of just actions, and just<br />

actions are those that promote public utility. The specific components of this science will<br />

be spelled out, below. But first it is important to note two main points: (1) Leibniz’s<br />

frequent methodological device, that of presenting definitions in a series, or “definition<br />

chain.” This is the first of a series that will include definitions of morality, right, and<br />

obligation. 34 (2) It is important not to take this particular series of definitions as evidence<br />

of Leibniz’s utilitarianism and voluntarism. 35 On the contrary, he is drawing Roman law<br />

into a fundamentally platonic (perhaps neo-platonic) moral-political tradition. His<br />

31 A.6.1.298.§10: “Personae enim et Res sunt facti, Potestas et Obligatio, etc. juris termini.” Note that<br />

Leibniz often seems to use potentia and potestas interchangably.<br />

32 Busche, p. 415 fn. 44: “Ein Rechtsfrage dagegen hat es mit normativen Kriterien zu tun und kann nur<br />

durch eine Deduktion oder Prüfung der Legalität (bzw. Legitimität) beantwortet werden.”<br />

33 A.6.1.300-301.§14: “Jurisprudentia est scientia acitonum [sic] quatenus justae vel injustae dicuntur.<br />

Justum autem atque injustum est, quicquid publicè utile vel damnosum est. Publicè, id est, primum Mundo,<br />

seu Rectori ejus Deo, deinde Generi Humano, denique Reipublicae.”<br />

34 A much longer definition chain will be analyzed in his Elementa Juris Naturalis.<br />

35 The passage might be taken in a voluntarist sense to mean that the just is what serve’s God’s interest and<br />

follows his will, and thus, as for Thrasymachus, justice ultimately serves the interest of the Superior (God,<br />

for Leibniz). However, as we will see, such a Thrasymachian interpretation leaves out Leibniz’s crucial<br />

qualifications, established early on, that God’s interest conform to reason and goodness, and must if God is<br />

to be revered. The meaning of ‘reason’ and ‘goodness’ does not depend solely on God’s will or power.<br />

God’s power lies in God’s capacity to distribute reason and goodness, within metaphysical limits.<br />

9

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!