28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Accordingly, the perfection of the will leads to the perfection of society. In this way we<br />

may understand that the metaphysical requirement for the best possible world has its<br />

foundation in the moral nature of rational substances, and has its theoretical foundation in<br />

the science of right.<br />

Section 5: Dissertation summary of conclusions<br />

I conclude this dissertation with a brief chapter-by-chapter summary of its main<br />

claims and findings. Beginning with Leibniz’s Nova Methodus Discendae Docendaeque<br />

Jurisprudentiae (1667), I focused on the definitions of right and obligation. Right (ius) is<br />

the moral power (potentia moralis) of a rational substance, and obligation (obligatio) is<br />

its moral necessity. Right and obligation thus denote the deontic “moral qualities” that<br />

enable a rational substance to act justly and to demand justice from others. A just act is<br />

that which promotes public utility. From this definition, Leibniz derives many others,<br />

most importantly, the three precepts or degrees of right (juris gradus). These are harm no<br />

one, give to each his due, and live honorably. These precepts, actually borrowed from the<br />

Roman Digest, and said to be the logical consequence of the definitions of right and<br />

obligation. I further showed that the objective requirements of the just (public utility) are<br />

also derived from this foundation of right. I should emphasize that the foundational<br />

importance of these definitions and their connection to the three precepts of right has not<br />

been analyzed at all in existing commentary on Leibniz. As I have argued, without<br />

understanding this foundation, Leibniz’s practical philosophy cannot properly be<br />

understood. This foundation must not be understood as deriving from the motives of love<br />

(either egoistic or non-egoistic), pleasure, happiness, or perfection. The foundation of<br />

right is deontically prior to these motives, and it provides the conceptual basis for the<br />

notions of freedom and necessity that pervade Leibniz’s moral and metaphysical thought.<br />

In Chapter Two, the detailed and extensive examination of the Elementa Juris<br />

Naturalis (1669-71) led to two important developments for Leibniz: the introduction of<br />

the notion of practical love into his theory of right, and his invention of a deontic or<br />

“juridical” mode of logic. My most important claim is that Leibniz introduces the notion<br />

of love as a descriptive motivational principle, so that the prescriptive (normative)<br />

demands of right may be fulfilled. The cause of this introduction is Leibniz’s attempt to<br />

defeat the skeptical claim that justice either does not exist or it is folly, since it either<br />

enjoins us to do another’s good (which no one would do) and to do it at one’s own<br />

expense (which is foolish). Two points are most important to be clear on: (1) Leibniz’s<br />

argument for the nature of justice as love, and the nature of love as pleasure, 38 seems to<br />

land him squarely upon hedonistic foundations. However, I argue that if ,pleasure is<br />

understood as fulfilling a psychophysical requirement for action, and that pleasure is the<br />

result but not the end of acts of justice, then the foundation, the a priori foundation is<br />

built squarely upon right. (2) The investigation of the terms right, just, and justice should<br />

lead us to pay careful attention to the distinct meaning and role of each of these terms in<br />

Leibniz, a point often missed by commentaries and translators: right (ius) is the moral<br />

power to do what is just; the just (iustum) is defined as an “equitable” relation between<br />

own and other good; and justice (iustitia) is the virtue of loving everyone justly. Leibniz<br />

believes that he arrives at these true definitions solidly by means of his epagogic<br />

38 Recall his definition of love: “To love is to find pleasure in the pleasure of another.”<br />

257

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!