28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

will be tacitly understood. Because, by the nature of things everything<br />

falls under possible to do or to omit, until a reasonable suspicion of the<br />

opposite arises. 173<br />

In sum, jurisprudence is a science, since it has been demonstrated out of the definition of<br />

‘the good person.’ It is a science of right, since it has been demonstrated out of the<br />

deontic categories of right and obligation, which correspond to the modal categories of<br />

possibility and necessity. The passage seems to express Busche’s remark that for Leibniz<br />

natural right is based on “the primacy of the possible.” Jurisprudence is the science of the<br />

just, and the just is what is possible for a good person to do, and that is to love everyone.<br />

The most basic elements of the science are freedom and duty. Obligation is now called<br />

“the science of duties,” and we can clearly see that he conceives of ‘potentia’, as moral<br />

possibility, since he says explicitly that the science of the just is what is possible and<br />

impossible for a good person. Thus, once again the whole of the science of jurisprudence<br />

is founded on the moral qualities, now conceived of as freedom and duty.<br />

That this science implies freedom can be seen in the definitions immediately<br />

following, where freedom and duty are moral powers in contrast to natural power:<br />

Freedom is the moral power or answerability in a good person congruent<br />

with natural power. Duty is the reduction of the natural power to the moral<br />

power. 174<br />

These definitions are, again, consistent with the logic of the modes of right. Freedom is a<br />

moral power, which includes the physical power of acting morally. Duty is the power of<br />

reducing or restraining one’s physical power. 175 Leibniz then reiterates the connection of<br />

the moral qualities with the modes of right:<br />

Therefore freedom is the mode by which acts are denominated either<br />

possible or contingent (or just and indifferent) for a good person. Duty is<br />

173 A.6.1.467: “IURISPRUDENTIA est scientia justi, seu scientia libertatis et officiorum, seu scientia juris,<br />

proposito aliqvo casu seu facto. Scientiam voco, etsi practicam, qvia ex sola definitione Viri boni omnes<br />

eius propositiones demonstrari possunt, neqve ab inductione exemplisqve pendent. . . . Iusti scientiam voco<br />

sue eius qvod viro bono possibile est, qvia eadem opera apparet et qvicqvid ei possibile non est facere, et<br />

qvicqvid ei possibile non est omittere. Scientiam officiorum voco, seu eius qvod viro bono impossibile et<br />

necessarium, id est omissu impossibile est, ... seu possibilia et contigentia habentur. Sufficit necessaria<br />

impossibiliaqve, imo sufficit impossibilia enumerari, inde caetera tacendo intelligentur. Qvia omnia per<br />

naturam rerum factu omissuve possibilia habentur, donec contrarii suspicio cum ratione oboriatur.”<br />

174 A.6.1.467: “Libertas est potentiae moralis seu cadentis in virum bonum congruitas cum naturali.<br />

Officium est defectus potentiae moralis à naturali.”<br />

175 This passage may be usefully compared with conceptions of subjective right found in Selden and early<br />

Hobbes, in which right is defined as the freedom to do whatsoever one will and is capable, without<br />

limitation, or with limitation determined only by God’s will, or by the law of nature. As Richard Tuck<br />

writes (p. 120): “Hobbes was quite explicit in the Elements that the state of nature was the state of total<br />

freedom hypothesised by Selden and the others: ‘Every man by nature hath right to all things, that is to say,<br />

to do whatsoever he listeth to whom he listeth, to possess, use, and enjoy, all things he will and can. For<br />

seeing all things he willeth, must therfore be good unto him in his own judgement, because he willeth them<br />

and may tend to his preservation some time or other . . . it followeth that all things may rightly also be done<br />

by him’” (Elements, I.14.10). Tuck also shows however that Hobbes in Leviathan limited this freedom<br />

somewhat.<br />

95

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!