28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

definitions . . . and propositions or precepts.” 163 Leibniz has at least made some effort to<br />

set out the definitions of right and their corresponding precepts, although we are left to<br />

fill in the gaps. His main purpose in doing so, however, is to correct the history of<br />

methodological failure to distinguish right from fact. 164 That is, he aims to establish a<br />

normative distinction between what is a matter of right and what is a matter of fact. In<br />

this sense, the method consists of establishing the a priori foundation of jurisprudence.<br />

Although Leibniz has not used the term “a priori,” this is clearly what he means.<br />

Jurisprudence is a science in the pure sense, established straight from the very definitions<br />

of things. 165 The problem, however, is that at this point Leibniz does not provide any<br />

argument for why these definitions are not merely nominal or arbitrary stipulations.<br />

Hobbes, as we have seen, defines right and obligation quite differently. But which<br />

definitions are “correct”? At this point Leibniz has not yet established a method for<br />

adjudicating among competing definitions. In the next chapter, however, we will see how<br />

he develops and carries out a much more rigorous method of deriving definitions.<br />

Another point relevant to his demonstrative method is that it is not clear that<br />

Leibniz’s definitions are entirely a priori, if by ‘a priori’ is meant ‘independent of any<br />

empirical premises.’ At times Leibniz, like Grotius and Aristotle, depends on the<br />

assumption that humans are naturally inclined to be social rather than egoistic, so that<br />

they will naturally seek a state of convenience and cooperation. But these assumptions<br />

are taken from observations about natural tendencies in humans, not from the definitions<br />

of the terms of right; and it does not appear possible to decide on the true nature of<br />

human beings solely by considering a priori definitions. Moreover, while we might agree<br />

that humans are by definition rational substances, it does not follow with deductive<br />

necessity that we have the moral qualities of right and obligation, since God could have<br />

given humans some other nature and some other qualities. The assumption that we are<br />

rational, social, rights-bearing beings could very easily be based on empirical<br />

observations about our tendencies and what best accords with them. This is however not<br />

a crucial criticism. Aspects of our natural physical constitution are after all part of what<br />

constitutes “natural law,” and Leibniz never denies this. Nor will he give up the search<br />

for a priori principles, nor for a way to make such principles compatible with the laws of<br />

our nature. As we will see, Leibniz often deals with two principles: one based on human<br />

physical nature and the other based on a priori reason. The problem is, however, that<br />

Leibniz has no straightforward way of clearly distinguishing between a posteriori and a<br />

priori in these matters.<br />

A final observation pertains to typical interpretations of Leibniz’s practical<br />

philosophy. A striking feature of the Nova Methodus is that it does not at all discuss the<br />

typical psychological motivations for action, such as happiness and pleasure, frequently<br />

found in Leibniz’s moral theorizing. The only motives discussed here are those connected<br />

with divine reward and punishment. Nor is the science of jurisprudence premised upon<br />

the requirements of metaphysical perfection, i.e., the maximization of reality. This is<br />

significant, since it is often assumed that Leibniz’s practical philosophy consists merely<br />

163 A.6.1.295.§6: “Jurisprudence Didactica, Elementorum nomine non ineptè appellabitur ad imitationem<br />

Elementorum Euclidis [...] Elementa duobus absolvuntur: Explicatione terminorum seu Definitionibus,<br />

quibus respondet titulus de verb. sign., et propositionibus seu praeceptis, quo pertinet titulus de reg. jur.”<br />

164 A.6.1.298.§10: “Et ut breviter dicam, est haec Methodus non ex juris sed Facti visceribus sumpta.”<br />

165 A.6.1.300.§14: “Demus igitur operam, ut solidam methodum ex ipsis rerum definitionibus eruamus.”<br />

40

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!