28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Notably, this is essentially Leibniz’s late position, as well. In this (1697-1700) revision<br />

note to the above passage, Leibniz clarifies and elaborates:<br />

(1) that no derivative notion is to be accepted unless it is explained, and<br />

(2) no derivative proposition unless it is proved. Explanation takes place<br />

through definition, proof through syllogism, which provides a conclusion<br />

by force of its form . . . and not everything necessary to the conclusion is<br />

expressed, in order to avoid tedium. But it is no small matter to have a<br />

way of reasoning infallibly on this basis if we do not avoid the effort<br />

involved. The rules of Descartes are less adequate, however. Certainly the<br />

first one—that what is perceived clearly and distinctly is true—is itself<br />

untrue (unless it be restricted on some ground) and proves, not existence,<br />

but only possibility. Nor is it very useful, unless we already have the<br />

criteria of clearness and distinctness which I once stated in a study on truth<br />

and ideas. (LL 91) 11<br />

The “study” Leibniz refers to is his Meditationes de Cognitione, Veritate, and Ideis<br />

(1684). Most important to note here is that both of these passages essentially characterize<br />

the Euclidean geometric method he will often allude to, if not employ, in the Nova<br />

Methodus and elsewhere: Definitions must be thoroughly analyzed to prove their<br />

possibility, i.e., the logical compatibility of their concepts; and propositions must be<br />

proven by demonstration; and demonstration consists of a chain of definitions. 12 In the<br />

Nova Methodus, Leibniz is hardly this rigorous; but he refines his method considerably in<br />

the Elementa Juris Naturalis, as we will see. Nevertheless, the definitions he does lay<br />

down here in the Nova Methodus are extremely important, since they establish, among<br />

other things, a normative distinction between “right” and “fact.” This distinction also<br />

depends on the distinction between “real” and “nominal” definition, and more broadly,<br />

corresponds with the metaphysical distinction between essence and existence. 13 I will<br />

return to these points below and in subsequent chapters. But the point to bear in mind is<br />

intended to refer. In any case, whether or not it agrees with Descartes, Leibniz’s position (better expressed<br />

in his later formulation, below) must be born in mind: you cannot prove the existence of something from a<br />

clear and distinct perception of it; you can only prove its possibility.<br />

11 A.6.1.279. Z.9: “(1.) Ut nulla notio derivativa admittatur, nisi explicata, (2.) ut nulla propositio<br />

derivativa, nisi probata. Explicatio fit per definitionem, probatio per Syllogismum vi formae concludentum<br />

. . . neqve omnia ad consequentiam necessaria exprimantur taedii vitandi causa. Interim non exigua res est,<br />

hac ratione habere nos modum infallibiliter ratiocinandi, si laborem non defugiamus. Regulae autem<br />

Cartesianae minus sunt sufficientes. Certè illa prima: qvod clarè et distinctè percipio verum est, nec vera est<br />

(nisi certa ratione circumscribatur), neqve enim existentiam sed tantum possibilitatem probat; nec valde<br />

utilis est, nisi clari et distincti criteria habeantur qvae indicavimus aliqvando in schediasmate de veritate et<br />

ideis.”<br />

12 I will examine Leibniz’s demonstrative method in much more detail in Chapter Four.<br />

13 These above passages show that Leibniz had always maintained that the existence of something cannot<br />

be proven from its mere possibility as an idea. This may seem surprising and inconsistent with some of his<br />

(later) major arguments, e.g., for the existence of a necessary being. However, I am interested only in how<br />

his theory and use of definitions affects his attempts to establish “real” definitions (of right and justice) as<br />

opposed to “nominal” and “arbitrary” definitions. This distinction between real and nominal definition is<br />

absolutely central, at every point of his career, to the grounds of his claims for right, morality, and justice.<br />

4

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!