28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

ight of war and punishment to the State. Within the State, the right of war is much<br />

reduced, although not entirely, by being managed under a just leader. 71 Leibniz does not<br />

offer an explanation for why we would give up the right of war, but presumably it is<br />

because the right is better managed by the State. 72 In sum, the rights and obligations of<br />

the State are grounded in the agreements of its citizens; but the source or authorization<br />

for the contract (or convention) itself is the moral quality of persons (rational<br />

substances). 73 These points are emphasized in §18.<br />

Whereby, all obligations resulting from the decisions of the legal body,<br />

including bodily and pecuniary punishments, pertain to the source of the<br />

contracts [my emphasis]. For, any subject of the Republic mutually<br />

promises to respect the State’s authority in such decisions, since it is the<br />

promise of fidelity that binds everyone to the contract. 74<br />

The source of the contract is thus the act of promising to hand over the right of<br />

punishment to the State. However, individuals retain their right to their own body, at least<br />

against unjust punishment. This promise of fidelity becomes “public right” (jus publicum)<br />

or the positive right of the public. The “end” of public right is “enforcement, which is the<br />

realization of the moral qualities, so that one who has the right of coercion or moral<br />

necessity, may also have the natural power.” 75 In other words, the end of public right is to<br />

actualize one’s natural moral power by means of the rights of punishment and restitution<br />

under the contract.<br />

At this point, the main definitional elements of Leibniz’s “science of<br />

jurisprudence” are in place, as he declares in §19: “Thus therefore we have deduced the<br />

highest source of the whole of Right.” 76 As reiterated in §20, “Therefore I judge the<br />

highest source of right to be sufficiently arranged with the most evident principles of pure<br />

right.” 77 This source is the moral qualities of right and obligation, from which are derived<br />

71 A.6.1.303.§17: “Sed in rebuspublicis, imo et aequitate duce ita restricta est haec licentia, ut laesus<br />

aestimatione debeat esse contentus, reservata Reipublicae poena si damnum consulto datum est. Injuria<br />

igitur fons est delictorum et quasi delictorum. Conventio vero promissiones acceptationesque omnes in se<br />

continet, quo pertinet doctrina de Verborum Interpretatione, Conditionibus, etc. Quasi contractus vero ad<br />

Jus reale pertinent. Multa vero quae ex his naturae fontibus non videntur descendere, sed ex Lege, illa<br />

omnia eo ipso ex eorum uno, nempe ex conventione descendunt, quia populus in Legislatorem<br />

compromisit.”<br />

72 Leibniz provides some explanation in §73, below.<br />

73 It is interesting to note that the State’s right to punish as grounded in the individual’s right to punish<br />

closely follows Grotius. As Tierney claims, “Grotius maintained that, since the power of the<br />

commonwealth came from its individual members, and since no one could confer a right he does not<br />

possess, the individuals must have possessed the right to punish before the state was formed” (Tierney<br />

333). Leibniz makes a similar argument in the Meditation.<br />

74 A.6.1.304.§18: “ Quare et omnes obligationes publicorum Judiciorum, sive ad poenam corporalem sive<br />

pecuniariam tendant, pertinent ad pactorum fontem; promisit enim quilibet subditus Reipublicae se decreta<br />

ejus vel universalia, ut leges; vel singularia, ut sententias; rata habiturum. . . . Ex ipso igitur Pacto<br />

promissae fidelitatis tenetur.”<br />

75 A.6.1.304.§18: “Cujus finis est executio, quae est realisatio qualitatum moralium, seu ut qui habet<br />

potestatem vel necessitatem moralem, habeat et naturalem.”<br />

76 A.6.1.304.§19: “Ita igitur universi Juris summa capita deduximus.”<br />

77 A.6.1.306.§20: “Ita igitur arbitror, summa Juris capita ex meri Juris evidentissimis principiis a me satis<br />

digesta esse."<br />

21

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!