28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

i.e., that she is the author of her action, rather than another person who put a compulsion<br />

on her. 22 An act is spontaneous when it springs from one’s own will. Similarly for<br />

Leibniz, spontaneity is a necessary condition of free will. 23 We can set aside for the<br />

moment whatever difficulties that these formulations may present. The point to take is<br />

that according to Leibniz Pufendorf’s account of obligation entails that one acts from<br />

external compulsion rather than internal spontaneity. Thus, one does not do one’s duty<br />

voluntarily. We will again encounter this notion of spontaneity, below. Secondly, and<br />

more devastatingly, on Pufendorf’s account if there is no superior to compel compliance<br />

with the law, then there is no obligation; therefore no justice. But this surely cannot be<br />

right, Leibniz holds, because justice (or rightness) must precede the imposition of a law.<br />

Thus Pufendorf’s entire jurisprudence rests on a fundamental mistake because it reduces<br />

to the imposition of a power whose justification is unexplainable.<br />

To see what is wrong with Pufendorf’s view requires a closer look at Leibniz’s<br />

understanding and criticism of it. While Pufendorf claims that obligation derives from the<br />

decree of a superior, he also claims that the superior must have just causes for the<br />

obligation. Leibniz argues that these two claims entail a vicious circle:<br />

Nor do I see how the author, acute as he is, could easily be absolved of the<br />

contradiction into which he falls, when he [derives all obligations of right<br />

from the decree] of a superior . . . while afterwards in Book 1, Chapter 2, §<br />

5, he states that to constitute a superior requires, not only that [superiors]<br />

possess the force of coercion, but also that they have a just cause to claim<br />

their power over me. Consequently, the justice of the cause is antecedent<br />

to this same superior, contrary to what had been asserted. Indeed, if a<br />

source of right requires a superior, and inversely, [if just causes of right]<br />

are necessary to constitute a superior, a circle is created than which none<br />

was ever more manifest. From what indeed will [just causes] be<br />

established, if no superior exists, from whom, supposedly, the right may<br />

emanate? (RP 73-4, some emendation) 24<br />

22 De Officio Lib. 1 cap. 1, § 10: “Quemadmodum autem hoc maxime nomine homo actionum suarum<br />

auctor habetur, quia isse voluntario eas suscepit, ita circa voluntatem id cum primus observandum, ejus<br />

spontaneitatem utique asserendam esse, saltem circa illas actiones, de quibus ab homine in foro humano<br />

ratio solet exigi. Ubi autem homini nihil plane spontaneitatis relinquitur, ibi non ipse homo, sed qui eidem<br />

necessitatem adfert, auctor habebitur actionis, ad quam homo invitus membra viresque suas accommodat.”<br />

23 Spontaneity is one of the three necessary conditions. The others are contingency (absence of logical<br />

contradiction) and intelligence. Spontaneity requires contingency and the absence of external constraint.<br />

G.7.109: “La Liberté est une spontaneité jointe à l’intelligence.” See also Theodicy §310: “Aristotle has<br />

defined [spontaneity] well, saying that ‘spontaneum est, cujus principium est in agente.’ . . . There also we<br />

have a mastery, individual and even perceptible, over our actions and our wills, resulting from a<br />

combination of spontaneity and intelligence.”<br />

24 D 4.281: “Nec video, quomodo actor, quamvis actutus, a contradictione facile excusari possit, quum<br />

omnem juris obligationem a superioris decreto derivat, . . . & tamen mox lib. I. c.2. § 5. ad superiorem<br />

constituendum requiri ait, non tantum, ut vires cogendi habeat, sed etiam ut justas habeat caussas<br />

vindicandi sibi in me potestatem. Ergo justitia caussae ipso superiore anterior est, contra quam<br />

adseverabatur. Nempe si ad juris originem opus est superiore, & rursus ad superiorem constituendum<br />

caussis opus est jure subnixis; circulus orientur, quo nullus umquam manifestior fuit. Unde enim constabit,<br />

justas esse caussas, si nullus adhuc superior exstat? a quo (scilicet) jus proficisci potest.”<br />

209

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!