28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

odies and of souls, and under whom masters are the fellow-citizens of<br />

their slaves, since the latter have the right of citizenship in the kingdom of<br />

God as well as their masters. One can say, then, that the body of a man<br />

belongs to his soul, and cannot be taken away from him while he is living.<br />

(RM 62) 85<br />

In other words, two main conditions preserve the right not to be harmed. One is a natural<br />

feature of us, our rational nature, by which we are free. This is, in effect, the condition of<br />

natural right in the subjective sense—rights are subjective attributes of us, not because we<br />

have unrestricted freedom, but because we are rational creatures capable of moral<br />

deliberation, action, and limitation. For this reason, one’s soul is the sole master of one’s<br />

body. The rights named above, then, cannot permit another master, and so forbid physical<br />

abuse. Secondly, Leibniz asserts a religious source for the obligation, seemingly a<br />

“creationist” source. Since God created us, he has a right to everyone as his possession.<br />

Therefore, in relation to God, all persons (slaves and masters) are equally subject to the<br />

same creator, and thus all have the same right not to be harmed. This also reflects<br />

Leibniz’s frequently expressed conviction that all rational souls are citizens in a republic<br />

of which God is the supreme monarch. 86 But Leibniz’s intention is not to depict God as<br />

the supreme voluntarist, but rather to assert that despite the apparent and contingent<br />

inequalities among humans, there is one quality in respect of which everyone is equal and<br />

which no one can justly violate—our internal freedom. This (God-given) moral freedom<br />

gives each individual the right to one’s body.<br />

The passage above (on M 62) suggests that the prohibition against abuse is also<br />

governed by a “stronger right.” This refers, actually, to a higher degree of right, as the<br />

following passage makes clear.<br />

But if I were to grant, contrary to the nature of things, that an enslaved<br />

man is the property of another man, the right of the master, however strict,<br />

would be limited by equity, which [means] that man [have] care for<br />

another man in the way that he would want others to care for him in a<br />

similar case, and by charity, which ordains that one should work for the<br />

happiness of others. And these obligations are perfected by piety, that is,<br />

by what one owes to God. (RM 63) 87<br />

85 M 68: ”Il sera toujours vrai qu’un autre droit plus fort s’oppose à l’abus de ce droit. C’est le droit des<br />

âmes raisonnables qui sont naturellement et inaliénablement libres, c’est le droit de Dieu qui est le<br />

souverain maître des corps et des âmes et sous qui les maîtres sont les concitoyens de leurs esclaves,<br />

puisque ceux-ci ont dans le royaume de Dieu le droit de bourgeoisie aussi bien qu’eux. On peut donc dire<br />

que la propriété du corps d’un homme est à son âme et ne lui saurait être ôtée, tant qu’il est en vie.” Leibniz<br />

may be following Ulpian here: “So far as the Civil Law is concerned, slaves are not considered persons, but<br />

this is not the case according to natural law, because natural law regards all men as equal” (“On Sabinus”,<br />

Book XLIII: 32).<br />

86 E.g., Discourse on Metaphysics sec. 36 and Monadology sec. 85.<br />

87 M 68: “Mais quand j’accorderais contre la nature des choses qu’un homme esclave est une propriété d’un<br />

autre homme, le droit du maître, quelqu’il pourrait être à la rigeur, sera limité par l’équité qui veut que<br />

l’homme ait soin d’un autre homme, tel qu’il voudrait qu’on eût de lui en pareil cas, et par la charité qui<br />

ordonne qu’on travaille au bonheur d’autrui. Et ces obligations sont perfectionées par la piété, c’est-à-dire,<br />

par ce qu’on doit à Dieu.”<br />

230

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!