28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The ordinary use of the word ‘property’ is slightly different from that, for it is<br />

taken to mean a person’s exclusive right to a thing. So even if there were no<br />

[individual] property, e.g. because everything was held in common, there could<br />

nevertheless be injustice. Also, in your definition of ‘property’ you mistake<br />

‘things’ to include actions as well; for otherwise, even if there were no [right<br />

concerning] things it would still be unjust to prevent men from acting as they need<br />

to. But that explanation makes it impossible that there should be no ‘property.’<br />

(NE 4.3.18.384) 75<br />

Essentially, Leibniz claims that Locke has not only misunderstood the meaning of<br />

property, but also the meaning of right. For Leibniz, right is a moral power, which<br />

includes the power of self-preservation without violating another’s right to the same. This<br />

right, as we saw in the Nova Methodus, is what makes the acquisition of property just. So,<br />

there is injustice without property; and since right precedes property, justice is always<br />

possible. Locke depends on the “facts” of property to determine whether justice can exist.<br />

But for Leibniz right and obligation determine what the facts ought to be. This once again<br />

shows that for Leibniz practical philosophy depends not on the relation between<br />

lawmaker and sanction, but on subjective right.<br />

The other proposition that Locke claimed to be demonstrable was, “No<br />

government allows absolute liberty.” 76 Since the ideas of ‘government’ and ‘absolute<br />

liberty’ are incompatible, we can determine with demonstrative certainty that this<br />

proposition is true. It is simply analytic. Leibniz agrees, but says only that the proposition<br />

“belongs to the corollaries.” This means that it depends on a more fundamental definition<br />

or axiom. But what does this mean? I think we can assume that the proposition is a<br />

corollary to the definition of subjective right. The definition of right authorizes<br />

governmental sanction as a means of restricting individual liberty. So, similar to the case<br />

on property, on Leibniz’s account of right it is impossible that government should grant<br />

absolute liberty. The impossibility depends on the (supposed a priori) definition of right,<br />

not on the definition of government. Leibniz does not pursue the point, but again his<br />

intention seems clear enough: demonstrations in the moral and political spheres depend<br />

not on the relation between lawmaker and sanction, or pleasure and pain, but on the<br />

relation between definition and law. It is the a priori definition of right that legitimizes<br />

government and its sanctioning powers.<br />

The remaining discussion deals with maxims and reveals no less than what<br />

Leibniz claims is a “fundamental maxim” that is drawn from “right itself” and is based on<br />

“pure reason.” This discussion takes place near the end of the Nouveaux Essais (Book 4<br />

Chapter 7, “Of Maxims or Axioms). It is important to understand what Leibniz means by<br />

‘maxim’, since he uses the term frequently and in different ways. Normally, a maxim is a<br />

precept or command. That is, the form of a maxim is an imperative. It can be recalled that<br />

75 NE 4.3.18.384: “On se sert du mot de proprieté un peu autrement pour l’ordinaire, car on entend un droit<br />

de l’un sur la chose, avec l’exclusion du droit d’un autre. Ainsi s’il n’y avoit point de proprieté, comme si<br />

tout étoit commun, il pourroit y avoir de l’injustice neantmoins. Il faut aussi que dans la definition de la<br />

proprieté, par chose vous entendiés encore action; car autrement, quand il n’y auroit point de droit sur les<br />

choses, ce seroit tousjours une injustice d’empecher les hommes d’agir où ils en ont besoin. Mais suivant<br />

cette explication il est impossible qu’il n’y ait point de proprieté.”<br />

76 Immediately following the above example, E 4.3.18.<br />

195

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!