28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

good person. (ii) The second component of the logic of right consists of the logical<br />

structures as a whole in relation to the logical structure of “traditional” logic, i.e., the<br />

alethic logic of possibility and necessity. In other words, the normative logic of right<br />

operates analogously, but independently, of traditional logic. This means that the moral<br />

qualities themselves are the basis for a normative logic, that is, a logic for moral freedom<br />

and virtue.<br />

In order to understand what Leibniz is doing, it is best to begin with some<br />

terminological clarifications, beginning with the “modes of right” (juris modalia). These<br />

modes are permissible, forbidden, obligatory, and omissible. They are typically used in a<br />

legal context to designate kinds of actions in relation to the law. 116 Thus, it is lawfully<br />

permissible to do X, obligatory to do Y, and forbidden to do Z. Leibniz however uses<br />

these modes in relation to a moral law, or rather, in relation to the definition of a good<br />

person. Thus, for example, it is morally permissible to do X; morally obligatory to do Y,<br />

and so forth, since X and Y are what the good person would do (i.e., perform some act of<br />

rational love). In addition, the logical relations among these modes operate similarly but<br />

differently from the “traditional” logical (or alethic) modes. 117 The alethic modes are<br />

called possible, impossible, necessary, possible not. These are the four types of alethic<br />

modal propositions of the Aristotelian square of opposition; but they are typically<br />

reduced to two types: necessary and possible (or contingent). The alethic mode<br />

categorizes propositions as either necessarily true or contingently true. For example, ‘A =<br />

A’ is necessarily true; while, ‘the jurisconsult is happy’ is contingently true. The logic of<br />

the modes of right and their relation to the alethic mode will be shown as we proceed. In<br />

sum, what Leibniz is doing here is taking juridical terminology, placing it under moral<br />

jurisdiction, so to speak, and giving it an a priori logic proper to norms of action, rather<br />

than things or states of affairs.<br />

We can now turn to the passages that begin Draft 5. 118 The first step is to see that<br />

Leibniz begins with a definition of justice in terms of virtue. “Justice is the habit of<br />

loving everyone.” 119 This definition is noteworthy for several reasons. As we saw, the<br />

definition with which he had concluded his epagogic induction in Draft 4 was: “Justice is<br />

the habit of loving others.” Thus the definition beginning Draft 5 represents a dramatic<br />

broadening in scope: Justice is not merely the habit of loving some others, but all others.<br />

However, we also noted that Leibniz seemed to define the just as “loving everyone.”<br />

Therefore, since justice is the virtue of doing what is just, justice must be the habit of<br />

loving everyone. It is important to connect this definition with another found at the very<br />

beginning of Draft 6: “Justice is the habit (or constant disposition) of the good person;<br />

116<br />

Leibniz, who received his Doctorate in law at the age of 20 with his dissertation De Casibus Perplexis in<br />

Jure (1666), was certainly familiar with this terminology. Quite possibly, the mode of obligation was first<br />

recorded by Justinian (533 AD, Institutiones, Book 3 Tit. 13): “Obligation is a bond of law with which we<br />

are bound by a necesssity of performing some act according to the laws of our state (obligatio est iuris<br />

vinculum, quo necessitate adstringimur alicuius solvendae rei, secundum nostrae civitatis iura).”<br />

117<br />

Logicians refer to the “traditional” or Aristotelian modes as “alethic,” or “ontic,” or simply “logical”<br />

modes. For consistency sake I will refer to the traditional modes only as ‘alethic.’ I will refer to Leibniz’s<br />

juris modalia as either ‘modes of right’ or ‘deontic modes’. The term ‘deontic’ seems to have been coined<br />

by G.H. von Wright (1951) or Ernst Mally (1926). See also von Wright (1971).<br />

118<br />

I have combined parts of Drafts 5 and 6 in a way that seems to me closest to Leibniz’s intentions and<br />

which presents the most orderly argument.<br />

119<br />

A.6.1.465: “Iustitia est habitus amandi omnes.”<br />

78

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!