28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

By a plan for studies we mean a certain kind of state of reason; that is, a<br />

method for arriving at a state of perfected actions. (LL 85) 7<br />

As a departure point for any field of inquiry (that is, as a plan for any faculty, such as<br />

theology, knowledge, and here, jurisprudence), Leibniz is above all concerned with<br />

method. The faculty of jurisprudence must utilize a method in two general ways, and<br />

these correspond to the two parts of the Nova Methodus: (1) a psychophysical method<br />

designed to promote the habit of acting virtuously; (2) a rational/geometric method<br />

designed to establish the rational grounds of right and virtue. The overall aim of the<br />

method is to perfect the actions and judgments of the jurisconsult. As he says in the<br />

second sentence: “This state [of perfected actions] is called habit, which I define as a<br />

permanent but acquired readiness to act” (LL 85). 8 This definition should be kept in<br />

mind, since in the Elementa Juris Naturalis Leibniz eventually comes to define justice as<br />

a virtue, that is, as a “constant disposition” or habit to do what is just. Throughout his<br />

writings, Leibniz retains this Aristotelian notion that justice is a virtue, indeed, “the<br />

whole of virtue,” 9 and this notion of virtue is contained in his ultimate definition of<br />

justice as “charity of the wise,” as we will see in Chapter Six.<br />

Crucially relevant to an understanding of Leibniz’s method in the Nova Methodus,<br />

as well as in all his texts, is what he calls here the “art of judging” or “analytics.” As<br />

shown here, Leibniz finds Descartes’ rules for method insufficient, and so he establishes<br />

his own rules.<br />

Analytics, or the art of judging, seems to me to be almost completely<br />

reducible to two rules: (1) no word is to be accepted without being<br />

explained, and (2) no proposition is to be accepted without being proved.<br />

These I believe to be far more absolute than the four Cartesian rules in the<br />

first Philosophy, the first of which is that whatever I perceive clearly and<br />

distinctly is true. This is deceptive in endless ways. (LL 88 § 25) 10<br />

7<br />

A.6.1.266: “Pars I. Generalis, caeterisqve Facultatibus communis. De ratione Studiorum in universum.<br />

§.1. Studiorum ratio est species quaedam Rationis Status, id est, modus perveniendi ad statum actionum<br />

perfectarum.”<br />

8<br />

A.6.1.266: “Status autem iste dicitur Habitus, qvem definio: Agendi promptitudinem acquisitam<br />

permanentem.”<br />

9<br />

AE Book V. 1129b30: “In justice is every virtue comprehended. And it is complete virtue in its fullest<br />

sense, because it is the actual exercise of complete virtue. It is complete because he who possesses it can<br />

exercise his virtue not only in himself but towards his neighbor also.”<br />

10<br />

A.6.1.279-80 : “Analytica seu ars judicandi, mihi quidem videtur duabus feré regulis tota absolvi: (1.) Ut<br />

nulla vox admittatur, nisi explicata, (2.) ut nulla propositio, nisi probata. Quas arbitror longè absolutiores<br />

esse, quàm quatuor illas Cartesianas in prima Philosophi, quarum primaria est, quicquid clarè distinctquè<br />

percipio, illud est verum: Quae infinitis modis fallit.” It is not clear, however, to which passage of<br />

Descartes Leibniz is referring. Loemker claims that Leibniz’s reference to “prima Philosophia” is incorrect,<br />

since the “four Cartesian rules” Leibniz refers to are in Discours de la méthod (LL 91). However, this claim<br />

also seems incorrect, since the first rule does not express what Leibniz says it does: “Le premier était de ne<br />

recevoir jamais aucune chose pour vraie que je ne la connusse évidemment être telle; c'est-à-dire, d'éviter<br />

soigneusement la précipitation et la prévention, et de ne comprendre rien de plus en mes jugements que ce<br />

qui se présenterait si clairement et si distinctement à mon esprit, que je n'eusse aucune occasion de le mettre<br />

en doute” (Discours, part 2 par. 18). Much closer to Leibniz’s reference is this passage from Meditationes<br />

de Prima Philosophia: “ac proinde jam videor pro regulâ generali posse statuere, illud omne esse verum,<br />

quòd valde clare & distincte percipio” (Med 3, par. 35). I take this to be the passage to which Leibniz<br />

3

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!