28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The principles of contradiction and identity, as we will see, are also the foundation of<br />

demonstrations. But these principles are true because all contradictions are impossible.<br />

That is, there is no possible world in which a contradictory proposition is true. 9 An<br />

identity (whose form ‘A = A’) is also said to be true since no further reason, other than<br />

non-contradiction, can be given for its truth. 10 Therefore, a proposition is said to be<br />

necessarily true when an analysis of its terms terminates in an identical proposition or is<br />

shown to be not contradictory. This is also what it means to demonstrate a proposition in<br />

a mathematical or geometrical sense. Below, we will see an example of mathematical<br />

demonstration (2 + 2 = 4).<br />

As just stated, the principles of necessary truths are contradiction and identity.<br />

But the principle of contingent truths is the principle of sufficient reason. Stated another<br />

way, propositions whose analysis of terms does not terminate but proceeds to infinity are<br />

called contingent truths. The containment of terms never results in an identity, and thus<br />

contingent propositions cannot be demonstrated in the strict sense of necessity.<br />

Epistemologically, this means that we finite knowers can never have absolute certainty of<br />

the reason for the connection between subject and predicate (or the containment of<br />

predicate in the subject); although, through experience we can be more certain. The<br />

connection is nonetheless metaphysically guaranteed, since it is known by God, who<br />

“grasps” the connection “in one intuition” (see quotations below). For example, the<br />

proposition, “Caesar crossed the Rubicon” is true if the concept ‘crossing the Rubicon’ is<br />

contained in the concept of ‘Caesar’. This proposition is in fact true, but it is not a<br />

necessary truth because its contrary ‘Caesar did not cross the Rubicon’ is not a logical<br />

contradiction. The latter proposition is therefore logically possible, i.e., logically<br />

contingent. A most important point, however, is that not only does God see the<br />

connection, but God determines the connection. That is, the fact of Caesar having crossed<br />

the Rubicon is a truth determined by God, who nevertheless, as Leibniz insists, freely<br />

chose this predicate to be included in the concept of Caesar.<br />

These distinctions are of enormous consequence for Leibniz’s philosophy,<br />

especially for his argument for divine and human freedom, issues about which there is<br />

much debate. 11 But here we need be concerned only with clarifying the use he makes of<br />

nor false” (NE 362).<br />

9 To be precise, Leibniz nowhere talks of “possible worlds” in reference to necessary truths. He only says<br />

that necessary truths are those whose contraries are impossible. This implies that there is no possible world<br />

in which they are true—although Leibniz does not say this. Nor does Leibniz say ‘necessary truths are true<br />

in all possible worlds’ although this is true. Here is an example of what he does say, in Corresondence with<br />

Clarke, 5 th letter sec. 10 p. 57: “Absolute and metaphysical necessity depend upon the other great principle<br />

of our reasonings, that of essences; that is, the principle of identity or contradiction: for, what is absolutely<br />

necessary, is the only possible way, and its contrary implies a contradiction.” See Margaret Wilson for the<br />

claim that Leibniz does not speak of possible worlds in reference to necessary truths.<br />

10 This is to say that the principles of identity and contradiction are indemonstrable, as I will explain below.<br />

11 For example, it may be thought that the distinction between necessary and contingent truths does not<br />

really work, since supposedly contingent propositions, such as “Caesar crossed the Rubicon,” really turn<br />

out to be necessary. According to the “complete concept” of a subject, if a subject lacks any one of his or<br />

her predicates, then that subject would be a different subject altogether; thus all predicates are essential<br />

(i.e., necessary) to the concept of the subject. But there is debate about whether Leibniz must be committed<br />

to the “complete concept” theory, whether it really does commit him to spinizistic necessity. Another point<br />

of controversy involves the criterion for God’s choice of the best possible world and whether the criterion<br />

142

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!