28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

let us summarize the “duplex” relationship between these foundational terms, right and<br />

obligation. These terms designate the moral qualities of a rational substance. An analytic<br />

relation holds between the meanings of right and obligation, such that one’s moral power<br />

entails obligations to be performed and granted. The necessity of this relation is grounded<br />

in the subjective capacity to recognize an objectively just moral order (public utility) and<br />

to determine oneself in accord with it. This implies the self-determining freedom of<br />

rational substances. Thus, a moral agent is one who is endowed with the capacity of<br />

making one’s right consonant with the right of all rational beings.<br />

The implications and plausibility of this position I attribute to Leibniz will be seen<br />

as we proceed. But before proceeding to §15, it is useful to compare these formulations<br />

with Hobbes’. While it would take us far afield to analyze Hobbes’ formulations<br />

thoroughly, it is sufficient to review his fundamental premises in Chapter 14 of Leviathan<br />

(1651), where he defines and resolves the relations among right, power, and obligation.<br />

Hobbes begins the chapter by distinguishing right (jus) from law (lex), in order to show<br />

that right includes the concept of Liberty, but does not include any restrictions, let alone<br />

obligations.<br />

The RIGHT OF NATURE, which Writers commonly call Jus Naturale, is the<br />

Liberty each man hath, to use his own power, as he will himself, for the<br />

preservation of his own Nature; that is to say, of his own Life; and<br />

consequently, of doing any thing, which in his own Judgement, and<br />

Reason, hee shall conceive to be the aptest means thereunto. (H 189)<br />

It is not always clear how far Hobbes intends this right or liberty to extend. Is it limited to<br />

bare self-preservation, or may it entail the right to anything whatsoever? Hobbes next<br />

defines ‘liberty’ as “the absence of externall Impediments: which Impediments, may oft<br />

take away part of a mans power to do what hee would” (H 189). This formulation does<br />

not seem to impose any limitation on liberty. For Hobbes, the only restriction on liberty<br />

comes from the law of nature, which is wholly distinct from the Right of nature, that is, in<br />

the same way that obligation is wholly distinct from liberty:<br />

A LAW OF NATURE, (Lex Naturalis,) is a Precept, or generall Rule, found<br />

out by Reason, by which a man is forbidden to do, that, which is<br />

destructive of his life, or taketh away the means of preserving the same. . .<br />

. For though they that speak of this subject, use to confound Jus, and Lex,<br />

Right and Law; yet they ought to be distinguished; because RIGHT,<br />

consisteth in liberty to do, or to forbeare; Whereas LAW, determineth, and<br />

bindeth to one of them: so that Law, and Right, differ as much, as<br />

Obligation, and Liberty; which in one and the same matter are<br />

inconsistent. (H 189)<br />

Hobbes is clear that Obligation is no part of the right of nature; indeed, obligation is<br />

inconsistent with the very concept of right. For this reason, the right of nature leads to the<br />

condition of war of every one against every one. Thus, “it followeth, that in such a<br />

condition, every man has a Right to every thing; even to one anothers body” (H 190).<br />

This is significant, since Leibniz, as we just saw, says that Liberty consists in the right to<br />

16

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!