28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

eward or fear of punishment, nor simply by the motives of pleasure or happiness. Here<br />

in the Nova Methodus, however, he indicates only the motive of reward and punishment.<br />

As mentioned in the passage above, strict right and equity may lack that vincula physica<br />

to move us to act honorably (with moral rectitude). Therefore, God has made honor<br />

coincident with utility, so that we may be moved to act honorably. As Leibniz says, “by<br />

his wisdom God determines rewards for the just and punishments for the unjust. And<br />

what he has determined to bring to completion, his omnipotence sets it through.” 140 This<br />

means that we may be motivated by the assurance that God will execute the natural right<br />

of reward and punishment. In this way, “piety” means the motivation brought about by<br />

the recognition of God’s power and justice.<br />

To conclude on piety, we find Leibniz making the rather bold claim (at this point)<br />

that the existence of God is the “ultimate foundation” of natural right:<br />

The existence then of the wisest and most powerful being, or God, is the<br />

ultimate foundation of natural right, which for us is demonstrated with<br />

mathematical certainty, and when shown to the public, will entirely<br />

dissipate the truth-covering clouds of the atheists. 141<br />

The claim that “God is the ultimate foundation of natural right” needs to be qualified,<br />

however. First, this does not at all imply that natural right has a voluntarist foundation.<br />

We have just seen that God’s power, superiority, and honorability lie principally in his<br />

wisdom. It should also be recalled that Leibniz had said back in §5 that natural theology<br />

is “a species of jurisprudence, universally understood.” This means that natural theology<br />

must at least conform to the principles of jurisprudence. 142 Therefore, God is the<br />

foundation of natural right, not by founding its meaning, but by executing its<br />

prescriptions. 143 The second qualification is that Leibniz does not here provide any<br />

argument, demonstrative or otherwise, for God’s existence; nor does he demonstrate that<br />

natural right derives from God’s existence, as he seems to suggest it does. However, he<br />

may very well be alluding to his earlier De Arte Combinatoria (1666), which includes his<br />

Demonstratio Existentiae Dei, ad Mathematicam Certitudinem Exacta. 144 A bit later in<br />

140 A.6.1.344.§75: “Quia Deum justis praemia, injustis poenas destinasse ex ejus sapientia constat: Et quae<br />

destinavit perfecturum omnipotentiae ratio evincit.”<br />

141 A.6.1.344-5.§75: “Existentia igitur Entis alicujus sapientissimi et potentissimi, seu Dei, est juris naturae<br />

fundamentum ultimum, quae a nobis mathematica certitudine demonstrata, cum prodibit in publicum,<br />

disjectura est penitus nebulas ab atheis veritati offusas.” In a late revision note Leibniz adds: “Juris Naturae<br />

simul fundamentum ultimum et fastigium supremum; in qvo theoreticae et practicae philosophiae supremae<br />

rationes conjunguntur, nisi alterius loci essent” (Z. 1-3. p. 345).<br />

142 Leibniz later agrees with Grotius, Bayle, and others, that in a sense the natural law would be valid even<br />

if God did not exist (Theodicy §§182-4). In Chapter Six I will explain how Leibniz reconciles this<br />

apparently inconsistent view.<br />

143 See also Schneider, H-P. (1967) p. 338: “Der Bereich des natürlichen Rechts (jus naturale, seltener: jus<br />

naturae) umfaßte sowohl die gesamte Ordnung des Seins, der göttlichen Schöpfung, so fern sie ihre<br />

Entstehung nicht dem göttlichen Willen (voluntas), sondern der Weisheit Gottes (sapientia Dei) verdankte<br />

und in der Natur der Dinge (natura rerum) begründet lag, als auch alle sich daraus ergebenden Tugenden<br />

und Pflichten, diese Ordnung zu erhalten. Demgegenüber zählte Leibniz zum Bereich des positiven Rechts<br />

(jus positivum, legitimum, voluntarium, arbitrarium) alle diejenigen Rechtsgebiete, deren konkrete<br />

Ausgestaltung von einem bestimmten, menschlichen oder göttlichen Willensentschluß abhängt.”<br />

144 A.6.1.169<br />

35

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!