28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

of these sources. In (1) the ground is reason itself; in (2) it is the will of a superior (either<br />

God or a human sovereign). Leibniz illustrates the point with this analogy: “Euclid is<br />

believed, not on the basis of what he says, but on the basis of what he proves, which is<br />

otherwise in divine and human laws, where the will stands in place of reason [ground].” 23<br />

In other words, this is an argument by analogy: geometry is not grounded in the will of<br />

Euclid, but in reason; just so, natural theology and jurisprudence are grounded, not in the<br />

will of God, but in reason. However, divine and positive law, as revealed in scripture and<br />

in the existing State, are grounded in the will of a superior—although the will is not,<br />

ultimately, the justificatory ground of law. Scripture and human law must reflect the<br />

science jurisprudence. In this sense, we can understand Leibniz’s striking claim:<br />

It is no wonder that what has come to jurisprudence, the same has come to<br />

be used in theology; for, theology is a certain species of jurisprudence,<br />

universally taken; it concerns namely Right and the maintaining of Laws<br />

in the State, or better, the reign of God over humans. 24<br />

Thus the science of jurisprudence “universally taken” means not merely a science for the<br />

jurisconsult of a particular State, but a science regulating the rule of a universal monarch,<br />

i.e., God. In its most encompassing form, jurisprudence is the science of God’s rule over<br />

humanity. This claim is significant for several reasons: (1) it places the principles of<br />

jurisprudence in a primary relation to theological principles, dictating, to some extent at<br />

least, what sort of being God must be; (2) it places jurisprudence in a primary relation to<br />

metaphysics, since the former dictates the sort of world, indeed, the sort of moral world,<br />

that God must create; (3) the claim conveys Leibniz’s lifelong position that power,<br />

whether it belongs to God, the sovereign, or the human subject, must be regulated by<br />

reason. 25 God has right as a moral power. This point is also relevant to the debate<br />

concerning voluntarism. Several commentators have claimed that Leibniz was a<br />

voluntarist in his early writings. However, the above passages (and others, as we will see)<br />

23 A.6.1.294.§4: “Euclidi non creditur quia dicit, sed quia probat, quod secus est in Legibus Divinus<br />

Humanisque, ubi stat pro ratione voluntas.” In a late revision note to this line Leibniz adds, “the will is not<br />

for those who change the laws; reasoning may be servicible to the interpretation of obscure laws; indeed,<br />

for the wise, the will never stands without reason [ground] (voluntas apud eos qvibus jus Leges mutandi<br />

non est; qvanqvam ratio etiam ad legis obscurae interpretationem inserviat ; nunqvam enim apud<br />

sapientem voluntas stat sine ratione).”<br />

24 A.6.1.294.§5 “Nec mirum est, quod in Jurisprudentia, idem et in Theologia usu venire, quia Theologia<br />

species quaedam est Jurisprudientiae universim sumtae, agit enim de Jure et Legibus obtinentibus in<br />

Republica aut potius regno DEI super homines;”<br />

25 Leibniz goes on in this section to explain that “in brief almost the whole of Theology depends for the<br />

greater part on Jurisprudence” (Breviter tota fere Theologia magnam partem ex Jurisprudentia pendet) p.<br />

295. He also refers the reader to his earlier, de Arte Combinatoria (1666), where he states, “Par in<br />

Theologica terminorum ration est, quae est quasi Jurisprudentia quaedam specialis, sed eadem<br />

fundamentalis ratione caeterum. Est enim velut doctrina quaedam de Jure publico quod obtinet in<br />

Republica DEI in homines” (A.6.1.190.31-33). See also, Nouveaux Essais, p. 526: “La Theologie traitte de<br />

la felicité eternelle et de tout ce qui s’y raporte, autant que cela depend de l’Ame et de la conscience, c’est<br />

comme une Jurisprudence qui regarde ce qu’on dit estre de foro interno et employe des substances et<br />

intelligences invisibles.” Schneider, H-P 1967, p.342) cites two letters, and especially Monita ad S.<br />

Pufendorfii (1706 Dutens 6.3.278): “. . . communesqve regulae utique in scientiam cadunt, & in<br />

jurisprudentia universali tradi debent, cujus praeceptis etiam theologia naturalis utetur.”<br />

7

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!